1 MORPHOSYNTAX OF COMPLEX PREDICATES IN SOUTH CAUCASIAN LANGUAGES by Leila Lomashvili _____________________ Copyright Leila Lomashvili 2010 A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the DEPARTMENT OF LINGUISTICS In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY In the Graduate College THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA 2010 2 THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA GRADUATE COLLEGE As members of the Dissertation Committee, we certify that we have read the dissertation prepared by Leila Lomashvili entitled Morphosyntax of complex predicates in South Caucasian languages and recommend that it be accepted as fulfilling the dissertation requirement for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy _______________________________________________________________________ Date: 04/14/2010 Heidi Harley _______________________________________________________________________ Date: 04/14/2010 Simin Karimi _______________________________________________________________________ Date: 04/14/2010 Andrew Carnie _______________________________________________________________________ Date: 04/14/2010 Rudolph Troike Final approval and acceptance of this dissertation is contingent upon the candidate’s submission of the final copies of the dissertation to the Graduate College. I hereby certify that I have read this dissertation prepared under my direction and recommend that it be accepted as fulfilling the dissertation requirement. ________________________________________________ Date: 04/14/2010 Dissertation Director: Heidi Harley ________________________________________________ Date: 04/14/2010 Dissertation Director: Simin Karimi 3 STATEMENT BY AUTHOR This dissertation has been submitted in partial fulfillment of requirements for an advanced degree at the University of Arizona and is deposited in the University Library to be made available to borrowers under rules of the Library. Brief quotations from this dissertation are allowable without special permission, provided that accurate acknowledgment of source is made. Requests for permission for extended quotation from or reproduction of this manuscript in whole or in part may be granted by the copyright holder. SIGNED: Leila Lomashvili 4 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS First of all, I would like to thank my advisors Heidi Harley and Simin Karimi in helping me to accomplish this goal and have been a part of all I have done at the University of Arizona Linguistics Department. They have been my mentors and to say more precisely, my virtual guides in every step I took during my study in the program. Heidi has been a role model, an inspiring and driving force of what I have accomplished in this dissertation and the qualifying papers, which have dealt with various aspects of the morphosyntax of South Caucasian languages. In these works, which naturally led to my dissertation topic, I learned from Heidi how to approach various linguistic phenomena to create the most comprehensive account within existing frameworks as well as to develop my own take on them. Likewise, I am particularly indebted to Simin in learning the structure and logic of linguistic argumentation and presenting it to a reader in the clearest form possible. Both of them have been extremely helpful during my work on the dissertation reading and giving comments on multiple drafts of chapters, and giving suggestive and pithy comments whenever I needed them. I also wish to thank my other committee members: Rudolph Troike and Andrew Carnie. I list them in a chronological order because it was Rudy who inspired me initially to pursue linguistics as a profession and particularly its theoretical aspect. I came to the Program of English Language and Linguistics at the University of Arizona as a master’s student of Russian to gain deeper understanding of linguistic theories and with the very first classes taken from Rudy Troike I got enchanted by the depth and scope of research in the field that Rudy presented. It was mainly he who advised me to venture into the profession of linguist and specialize in theoretical morphosyntax, a field I fell in love with during his lectures. Andrew has been my chief inspiring figure throughout my entire career in the Linguistics Department and particularly, in the first year when I became fascinated with his homeworks and linguistic tasks completed every week in his introductory Syntax course. I remember those assignments as most challenging and at times provoking strong emotions by solving them. Andrew was the first instructor in syntax who supported my decision to major in syntax/morphology and probably defined my future for many years to come. I would like to thank all these people for all their extraordinary support in all I have been through these years. Also, I want to thank many of my linguist friends and particularly, Elly van Gelderen in her inspiring support during my Doctoral career. I benefited immensely with her indepth comments on my qualifying papers and wise questions during my presentations at the conferences. Without her, many of my achievements in this program would not be possible. I also want to extend my gratitude to my instructors and co-instructors in the Linguistics department: LouAnn Gerken, Cecil McKee, Amy Fountain, Ying Lin, Mike Hammond, Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini, Diana Archangeli, Tom Bever, Adam Ussishkin and many others in inspiring and directing me toward this goal. The discussion of various parts of this work with my friends and classmates at different times has also been extremely useful and without the following people this project would not be probably possible: Tatyana Slobodchikoff, Mercedes Tubino, Alan Hogue, Brian Gordon, Collin 5 Gorrie, Shannon Bischoff, and friendship with Sumayya Racy, Lindsay Butler, Jaime Parchment, Amy LaCross, Jeff Punske, Yosuke Sato, Jared Francom, Michael Anderson, Mans Hulden, Dan Siddiqi, Jae-Hoon Choi, Jae-Hyun Sung, Sylvia Reed, Greg Key, Deniz Tat, Dana Osborne, and many others in the Linguistics and Anthropology Departments. I want to thank my friends outside of academia for being so supportive in my pursuits for many years: Paulette Williams, Ken Walker, Yang Yang, Nino Buachidze, Nino Amiridze. My family deserves a special tribute as it has been a major driving force behind my efforts all these years: my parents, mom, Lamara and dad, Anzor for their patience and inspiration, my twin brother Koba without whom this dissertation would be impossible and my sister Tsisana with her constant encouragement and love. Their contribution to my success is invaluable and cannot ever be sufficiently repaid no matter how much effort I will put to it in the future. Finally, I wish to thank my mom for her love and support. This dissertation is dedicated to her. 6 TABLE OF CONTENTS LIST OF TABLES………………………………………………………………………..9 LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS AND SYMBOLS ……………………………………….10 ABSTRACT……………………………………………………………………………..12 CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION………………………………………………………..13 1.0 Goals of the dissertation…………………………………………………………...13 1.1 Theoretical approaches to the study of complex predicate constructions……………………………………………………………………...14 1.2 Argument structure of causative and applicative constructions ………………….18 1.2.0 Introduction…………………………………………………………………..19 1.2.1 Argument structure of causatives…………………………………………….19 1.2.2 Argument structure of applicatives…………………………………………..22 1.3 Variation of causatives and applicatives in terms of complement size…………...26 1.4 Theoretical framework……………………………………………………………30 1.4.0 Distributed Morphology (DM)……………………………………………...30 1.4.1 Chomsky’s (1999, 2001) notion of phases …………………………………35 1.4.2 Contextual allomorphy as evidence for phasehood (Embick 2009)………………………………………………………………36 1.4.3 Kratzer (1994) on the VoiceP and external arguments……………………...39 1.4.4 Cuervo (2003) on different flavors of little vs………………………………42 1.5 Status of templates and assumptions about the morphosyntax of Georgian and related languages………………………………………………..44 1.5.0 Structure of the verbal template……………………………………………...45 1.5.1 Assumptions about language-specific templatic constraints………………...50 1.6 Case and agreement with various classes of verbs……………………………......52 1.7 Outline of the dissertation…………………………………………………………57 CHAPTER 2 CAUSATIVE ALTERNATIONS IN GEORGIAN AND RELATED LANGUAGES…………………………………………………………...60 2.0 Introduction………………………………………………………………………..60 2.1 Organization and outline of analysis……………………………………………....60 2.2 Assumptions……………………………………………………………………….62 2.3 Inchoative-causative alternation…………………………………………………..66 2.3.0 Introduction…………………………………………………………………..66 2.3.1 Causatives of inchoative verbs……………………………………………….67 2.4 Unergative verbs of various types and their causatives…………………………...72 2.4.0 Hale & Keyser (2002) on unergatives and Noun-Incorporated vPs………………...........................................................................................72 2.4.1 Adjective-Incorporated vPs and their causatives…………………………....78 2.4.2 Syntactic and iterated causatives of unergative verbs……………………….82 7 2.5 Transitive/causative alternation………………………………………………….. 88 2.5.0 Introduction…………………………………………………………………...88 2.5.1 X makes Y do V alternation…………………………………………………..89 2.5.2 Iterated causatives………………………………………………………….....95 2.6 Adversity causatives in Georgian………………………………………………..100 2.7 ‘Pretend’-type predicates and their causatives…………………………………...110 2.7.0 Introduction………………………………………………………………….110 2.7.1 Derivation of ‘Pretend’-type complex verbs………………………………...111 2.7.2 Causative alternation of ‘pretend’-type verbs…………………………….....115 2.8 Psych verbs and causative alternation…………………………………………....119 2.8.0 Empirical base of state, dynamic passive, and activity Psychological predicates……………………………………………………119 2.8.1 Analysis of the morphosyntax of psych verbs and their causatives………....126 2.9 Causative predicates in related languages (Mingrelian and Svan)………………132 2.9.0 Causative alternation is Svan………………………………………………..132 2.9.1 Causative alternation in Mingrelian………………………………………....136 2.10 Conclusions……………………………………………………………………..138 CHAPTER 3 APPLICATIVES AS COMPLEX PREDICATES……………………....141 3.0 Introduction……………………………………………………………………....141 3.1 Theoretical goals…………………………………………………………............141 3.1.0 Outline of the chapter………………………………………………..……..141 3.1.1 McGinnis (2004) on applicative structures and phases…………………....145 3.1.2 Transitivity restriction on high and low applicatives (Pylkkanen 2002)………………………………………………………….149 3.1.3 Cuervo (2003) on low and high applicatives in Spanish…………………..152 3.2 Low applicatives in Georgian……………………………………………………159 3.2.0 Introduction………………………………………………………………...159 3.2.1 Low Recipient applicatives………………………………………………...159 3.2.2 Low Source applicatives…………………………………………………...170 3.2.3 Low state applicatives: Possessor Datives (AT)…………………………...172 3.3 Low applicatives of unaccusative and inchoative verbs………………………....176 3.3.0 Introduction………………………………………………………………...176 3.3.1 Empirical data and syntactic analysis………………………………...........178 3.3.2 Analysis of morphological marking ……………………………………….183 3.4 Low applicatives of Noun/Adjective-Incorporated predicates…………………..186 3.5 Reflexive applicatives……………………………………………………………190 3.5.0 Introduction…………………………………………………………………190 3.5.1 Analysis of morphosyntax of reflexive applicatives………………………..194 3.6 Possessor Datives as low applicatives…………………………………………...198 3.6.0 Introduction………………………………………………………………...198 3.6.1 Low applicatives of stative eventualities…………………………………..199 3.6.2 Other applicative verbs in applicative constructions………………………203 8 3.7 Four-place predicates as hybrid type applicatives……………………………….205 3.7.0 Introduction………………………………………………………………...205 3.7.1 Analysis of morphosyntax of four-place applicatives……………………..210 3.8 High applicatives in Georgian…………………………………………………...215 3.8.0 Introduction………………………………………………………………….215 3.8.1 High applicatives with stative unaccusative predicates……………………..216 3.8.2 High applicatives with other unaccusative predicates………………………220 3.8.3 High applicatives with dynamic activity verbs…………………………….. 223 3.9 Applicatives in related languages (Mingrelian and Svan)………………………..227 3.9.0 Introduction…………………………………………………………………227 3.9.1 Applicatives in Mingrelian…………………………………………………227 3.9.2 Aplicatives in Svan…………………………………………………………235 3.10 Conclusions………………………………………………………………………240 CHAPTER 4. CONCLUSIONS………………………………………………………..242 APPENDIX A. HOMOPHONY ACROSS PHONOLOGICAL EXPONENTS OF VARIOUS MORPHEMES IN GEORGIAN………………………….245 REFERENCES………………………………………………………………………... 248 9 LIST OF TABLES TABLE 1. Morphological template of the Georgian verb…………………………. …...46 TABLE 2. The structure of the series in Georgian………………………………………53 TABLE 3. Case marking of transitive verb arguments………………………………….53 TABLE 4. Georgian agreement morphology…………………………………………….55 TABLE 5. Transitive and causative predicates in Mingrelian………………………….136 TABLE 6. Morphological marking of causatives of various verb classes……………..139 TABLE 7. Low applicatives in Georgian……………………………………………....144 TABLE 8. High applicatives in Georgian………………………………………………145 10 LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS AND SYMBOLS 1, 2, 3- Person agreement features in verbs Abs- Absolutive case Acc- Accusative case AOR- Aorist series APPLIC- Applicative/version morpheme CAUS- Causative morpheme CL- Clitic Dat- Dative case DER- Derivational affix Erg- Ergative case Evid- Evidentiality marker FUT- Future tense Gen- Genitive case INF- Infinitive marker Instr- Instrumental case Loc- Locative case Nom- Nominative case NONACT- Nonactive Voice marker NPN- Nominalizer affix O (with numbers) – Object Obl- Oblique case Pass- Passive Voice marker PAST- past tense mamker PERF- Perfective series PL- Plural number 11 Post- Postposition PRES- Present series Pretend- Pretend-type functional head PREV- Preverbal affix denoting aspect, direction, or the intensity of an event REECIP-Reciprocal marker REFL- Reflexive Voice morpheme S (with numbers) – Subject Sg- Singular number SCR- Screeve marker SER- Series marker SUBJ- Subjunctive mood marker TAM- Tense/Aspect/Mood marker TH- Thematic markers Tns- Tense morpheme VOICE- Voice marker 12 ABSTRACT The argument structure of complex predicates such as causatives and applicatives is closely associated with the functional heads that introduce core and non-core arguments: Voice, causative and applicative. These elements merge in a sentence structure at various cycles of derivation and take complements whose ‘size’ accounts for the meaning and thematic interpretations of these arguments. This thesis shows that the variation in the meaning of causatives and applicatives is not so much due to the morphological realization of the relevant heads in these predicates (causative and applicative) ,but rather the complement ‘size’ and the place where these heads are introduced. Specifically, lexical causatives result from the CAUSE head selecting for a RootP complement while syntactic causatives include two CAUSE heads taking argument-full vP as their complement and these CAUSEs are realized by separate phonological exponents at the Morphological Structure. In applicatives, Goal, Recipient or possessor interpretations may be obtained not only for non-core applied arguments in double-object constructions but for the highest external arguments of two-place predicates and also, for dative internal arguments of internally-caused events. It is argued that external arguments take on the meaning of non-core applied arguments in double-object constructions due to the different type of Voice head such as reflexive. The morphological realization of these predicates is distinct from the ones in which applied arguments represent additional, noncore elements of DOCs. The thesis shows that along with the change in morphology the syntactic structure of various types of applicatives accounts for the resulting meaning of complex predicates. 13 CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION 1.0 Goals of the dissertation This dissertation focuses on the morphosyntax of complex predicate constructions in three polysynthetic languages of the South Caucasian language family: Georgian, Mingrelian, and Svan. In this work, I follow Baker (1996) who defines complex predicates as verbal structures containing at least two morphemes each marking a phrasal argument in the -grid. According to this definition, complex predicates include the causative, applicative, and possessor raising structures. The focus of this dissertation is limited to causative and applicative constructions. This is partly because the morphological varieties of such constructions in these languages are sufficiently diverse so that they could be treated in a work of this scope. Also, causatives, and applicative structures have certain morphological similarities in that they contain morphemes indexing both core and non-core arguments in their theta-grid, such as the external argument, theme, and the goal/benefactee arguments. In addition to this similarity, these constructions are viewed as syntactically and morphologically complex structures, containing a minimum of two phrasal arguments, and at least two morphemes. Stemming from the above definition of complex predicates, the primary goal of the dissertation is to explore the formal properties of causative and applicative constructions and to account for mismatches that arise between the syntax-semantics and the morphology of these constructions. Such mismatches are common cross-linguistically. They abound even in languages which do not morphologically mark the causative, 14 applicative, or any other alternation. An example of such a mismatch is when instead of the causative or applicative morpheme itself, a Vocabulary Item (VI) realizing some other functional head in the left periphery of the clause shows up (such as reflexive, or voice) to mark the causative or applicative alternation. Therefore, the goal of this work is to propose a unified theory of how the meaning is encoded in syntax and morphophonology. The interface between these systems in causative and applicative constructions will be subject to scrutiny in Chapters 2 and 3 of this dissertation. 1.1 Theoretical approaches to the study of complex predicate constructions The syntax-all-the-way-down approach of Distributed Morphology is adopted here. This approach is relatively recent and has been initiated and advocated by Baker (1985, 1988), Halle & Marantz (1993, 2002), Marantz (1997), Travis (2000), Pylkkänen (2002), Cuervo (2003), and Harley (1995, 2008) among others for a wide range of verbal and nominal constructions, including causative and applicative constructions. This approach has a single engine of structure creation for both word and sentence formation. Consequently, lexical-semantic representations are syntactic representations, and no mapping problems arise between them. This contrasts with lexicalist approaches (for example, Levin & Rappaport Hovav 1995), where lexical complexity has been argued to be different from the complexity at the sentential level. Lexicalist approaches posit a need for linking rules specifying how lexical-semantic representations map onto the syntax. Take the following linking rule from Levin & Rappaport (1995): (1) Linking rules a) “Break: [[ x DO-something] Cause [y become BROKEN] 15 b) Immediate Cause Linking Rule The argument of a verb that denotes the immediate cause of the eventuality described by the verb is its external argument” (Levin & Rappaport Hovav 1995:135). c) “Directed change Linking Rule “The argument of the verb that corresponds to the entity undergoing the directed change described by that verb is its internal argument” (Levin & Rappaport Hovav 1995:146). These types of rules were considered to connect the autonomous modules of the grammar where lexical-semantic and syntactic representations are processed. The underlying idea of the lexical-semantic approach is that certain semantic notions are relevant to determining a verb’s argument structure. For example, in causative constructions, the potential adicity of a verb is determined based on the distinction between internally- and externally-caused events. The verbs denoting internally caused changes of state (such as flower, bloom, blossom, and decay in English) in which the cause is inherent to the natural course of development (Levin & Rappaport Hovav 1995, henceforth, L & RH), resist the causative alternation cross-linguistically: (2) The verbs of internal change resist causativization a. Cactus bloomed/blossomed/flowered early. b. * The gardener bloomed/blossomed/flowered the cactus early. (L & RH, 1995: 97) In contrast to these verbs of internal causation, externally-caused eventualities may be both transitive and intransitive. These regularly have transitive causative counterparts. Nevertheless, there are exceptions: (3) Verbs of external change resist causativization 16 a. The baker cut the bread. b. *The bread cut. c. The assassin murdered the senator. d. *The senator murdered. Thus, the lexical semantic properties of events, such as internal and external causation, are of crucial importance in determining whether the verb can participate in the argument structure alternation. L & RH argue that this distinction between externally and internally-caused events roughly corresponds to the unaccusative/unergative distinction too. Many unergative verbs denote internally-caused events while unaccusatives generally are derived from externally-caused verbs. Based on this correspondence then, it follows that unergative verbs may not participate in the causative/inchoative alternation, as illustrated by the impossibility of causatives in the following English pairs: (4) Causatives of unergative verbs are not possible a. Sheila laughed. b.* Sheila laughed John. c. Jack danced. d. *Jack danced Sheila. However, L & RH argue that languages that mark the causative alternation morphologically often allow causatives of internally-caused events, as in the Hebrew examples in (5): (5) Hebrew causatives a. Hu rakad. He danced ‘He danced.’ 17 b. Ha-nagan hirkid The-musician made.dance ‘The musician made him dance.’ oto. him c. Hu rac. He ran ‘He ran.’ d. Ha-meamen heric oto. The-coach made.ran him ‘The coach made him run.’ (L & RH 1995: 98) Chapter 2 of this dissertation shows that unergative verbs in Georgian and related languages can participate in the causative alternation without any restriction, regardless of their lexical semantics. Similarly, verbs of appearance and existence (such as exist, appear, emerge, etc.), which have been argued to resist causativization crosslinguistically, do participate in the causative alternation in the languages under investigation here. I argue that lexical-semantic approach does not give sufficient clearcut criteria for the classes of verbs participating in this alternation. Hale & Keyser’s (henceforth, H & K 1993) approach removes the need for the linking rules between the argument structure and lexical semantic interpretations, as the latter is the same as the argument structure (a welcome consequence for the simplification of the architecture of the grammar). This theory takes the syntax of word and sentence derivations as the source of compositional meaning of complex expressions. The rest of the chapter is organized as follows: in Section 1.2, the argument structure of causative and applicative constructions is introduced; Section 1.2.1 discusses the argument structure of causatives, and Section 1.2.2 the structure of applicatives; Section 18 1.3 explains the source of syntactic variation in causatives and applicatives; the theoretical framework of the research carried out in the dissertation is discussed in Section 1.4, which includes an overview of the framework of Distributed Morphology, Chomsky’s (1999, 2001) notion of phases, Embick’s (2009) theory of contextual allomorphy; Cuervo’s (2003) analysis of event-introducing heads (the varieties of little vs) along with Kratzer’s (1994) instantiation of VoiceP is presented; Section 1.5 discusses some basic background facts of verbal morphology and the status of templates in Georgian and in linguistics theory in general; Case and agreement morphology with various classes of verbs are discussed in Section 1.6 and the outline of the dissertation concludes the chapter in Section 1.7. 1.2 Argument structure of causative and applicative constructions 1.2.0 Introduction Most work on syntax-semantics of argument structure is based on the idea that verbs express different types of eventualities and that arguments express participants in events. This idea naturally extends into a claim that the relations between verbs and arguments, and between arguments themselves are built out from event structure, i.e. event types and predicates that verbs express (Davidson, 1967). In (6a), for instance, the cause event described by the verb melt relates the subject John to the event of ice melting, while in (6b), the object argument of (6a) relates to the event of melting, but in this case without any causing event: (6) Causative/inchoative alternation of English a. John melted ice. b. Ice melted. 19 It is evident that the event structure in (6a) is more complex since it combines two events: the causing and melting. Moreover, the two arguments (John and ice) are related to this complex event, while in (6b) only one argument is related to the simplex event of melting (ice). These two types of events illustrate a syntactic alternation referred to in the literature as the inchoative/causative alternation. Consider next how the dative argument expressing the possession or the Benefactive/Recipient relation is licensed in the following: (7) Applicative alternation a. John bought Anne a pastry. b. John bought a pastry. (Adapted from Levin & Rappaport 1995) In these sentences, the event structure is not composed of two separate events, as in (6a), where the verb combines the causing and the melting events. So we need to determine what is licensing the arguments in this construction. The insights incorporated in the analysis of the argument structure of complex predicates in this work are mainly drawn from H & K’s (1993) work and developed by, among others, H & K (2002), Borer (1994), Harley (1995), Marantz (1997), Travis (2000), Nash (2002), Pylkkänen (2002), and Cuervo (2003). Within this framework, syntactic elements such as functional heads and DPs are the building blocks of event structure, whose meaning is interpreted compositionally. In what follows, I present some basic assumptions about the argument structure of these constructions. 1.2.1 Argument structure of causatives 20 Hale & Keyser (1993, 2002), among others, posit that the argument structure of causatives involves an additional argument that is interpreted as a causer of the event described by the verb. The following sentences from English and Georgian illustrate this: (8) English a. Inchoative b. Causative The cake baked. Lisa baked the cake. (9) Georgian a. Inchoative ‘Kart’opili da- lp’a. Potato Prev-rotted ‘Potatoes rotted.’ b. Causative dato-m kart’opili dadato-Erg potato ‘Dato rotted potatoes.’ alp’o prev- CAUS- rotted As seen in (8)-(9), the inchoative/causative alternation involves the addition of the causer argument to the argument structure of a one-place inchoative verb. Syntactically the causative structures in these examples are non-distinct in English and Georgian. However, morphologically we see a difference. In Georgian, the causative head in inchoative/causative alternation is marked morphologically (affix a-), while in English it is not. Chapter 2 explores the conditions on the realization of this morpheme in Georgian and whether there is a correlation between the syntax of causatives and their morphological shape. I follow Pylkkanen (2002) in claiming that the causative head need not introduce the causer argument, and that causativization does not always increase the number of a verb’s syntactic arguments (Pylkkänen 2002:75). Rather the causative head (CAUSE), introduces a syntactically implicit event argument that contributes to the semantics of the 21 causative verb. Pylkkänen considers two sources of variation in terms of argumentprojecting properties of the causative head: in languages like Finnish and Japanese, where the CAUSE is independent of the Voice 1, the CAUSE never introduces a causer. Instead, in these languages, she argues that the causer is projected by the Voice head (Marantz (1986), Kratzer (1994) among others)). In English, by contrast, since the CAUSE bundles with the Voice0 as a single syntactic head, both introduce causative event semantics and the causer argument. Observe these differences in (10): (10) Variation in Voice-bundling in causatives (Pylkkänen 2002:76) a. Non-Voice-bundling causative b. Voice-bundling causative (Japanese, Finnish) (English) X2 Voice CAUSE X [Voice, CAUSE] Georgian and related languages with their non-zero CAUSE morphemes fit the typology of languages with the non-Voice bundling causative head. The relevant question is what evidence supports the separation of CAUSE from Voice in languages like Japanese, Finnish, Georgian, etc. Pylkkänen identifies Japanese adversity and Finnish desiderative causatives as structures where the causer argument is not projected at all even by the Voice head. In these constructions, the nominative subject is interpreted as an affected argument of the event described by the verb, but not as a causer: (11) Japanese adversity causative Taroo-ga musuko-o Taro-Nom son-Acc 1 2 sin-ase-ta. die-CAUSE-PAST See Section 1.6.4 for the motivation why the little v head is distinct from Voice. X in (7) is an external causer argument projected by the Voice0. 22 (i) ‘Taro caused his son to die.’ (ii) ‘Taro’s son died on him.’ 3 (Pylkkänen 2002: 81) Taro is introduced neither by the CAUSE head, nor by Voice0, as the adversity causative lacks external arguments. The causing event is clearly present and morphologically the CAUSE is realized as –(s)ase, but this head does not relate any participant to the causing event. Pylkkänen demonstrates that the separation of the CAUSE from the Voice is a natural consequence of the inability of CAUSE to introduce a causer argument in languages which have similar structures. In chapter 2, I pursue a similar analysis of the CAUSE in adversity causatives (in which CAUSE does not introduce an external argument), but the analysis is still different from Pylkkanen’s in that, in Georgian, adversity causatives are productive and their meaning is predictable. This will be argued to be a result of their syntax, specifically, the kind of complement that the CAUSE takes in these structures. To summarize my assumptions about causative constructions: (12) a. causative structures universally contain the causative functional head (CAUSE) and this head introduces a syntactically implicit event argument; b. the causer argument may or may not be introduced into the structure; c. in adversity and desiderative causatives where an external argument is not introduced, the nominative argument is often interpreted as affected by the event expressed by the verb. 1.2.2 Argument structure of applicative constructions 3 Pylkkanen (2002) argues that the adversity causatives generally are not productive structures like syntactic causatives in Japanese. Instead, they represent a variety of non-productive lexical causatives whose meaning may be ambiguous between two interpretations as illustrated in (11). Adversity causatives in Georgian and related languages do have a predictable meaning and they are productive, as will be shown in Section 2.6. 23 This section introduces some core assumptions about the argument structure of applicatives. Applicatives generally are defined as double object constructions in which besides the lexical (VP) and event-introducing verbal projections (vP), which may introduce arguments, the ‘additional’ functional head (Appl0) adds an ‘applied argument’. Usually, semantic relations are established either between this applied argument and the theme, or between the applied argument and an event described by the verb (Pylkkänen 2002, Cuervo 2003). The first relation, between a non-core applied argument and the theme, cross-linguistically is conceptualized as that of a stative possessor, a recipient, or a source (Cuervo 2003). These relations are referred to as the low applicative due to the lower merging site of the Appl0 head, namely, below VP: (13)a. Low Recipient applicative Sheila baked John a cake. b. Low Source applicative (Finnish) Liisa myi Mati-lta talo-n. Liisa.Nom sold Mati-Abl house-Acc ‘Lisa sold Matti’s house’. (Lit: ‘Lisa sold a house from Matti’.) c. Low Possessor applicative (Spanish) Pablo le admira la paciencia a Valeria Pablo CL.DAT admires the patience.ACC Valeria.Dat ‘Pablo admires Valeria’s patience.’ (Lit: Pablo admires Valeria the patience). Although the meanings of these expressions are different from each other, the structural relation between the applied argument and the theme is similar as shown in the following: 24 (14) VoiceP Low Applicative DPNOM/ERG Ext. Arg. vP v0 VP V0 ApplP DPDAT Appl.Arg. Appl’ Appl0 DPACC Theme By contrast, the high Appl0 head takes the VP as a complement. In high applicatives, the semantic relations are different: an applied argument may be experiencing or undergoing the effects of an event expressed by the verb, but in no way does the applied argument enter into a direct semantic relation with the theme and obtain the thematic interpretations of benefactee, recipient, etc. Observe the examples and the syntax of this relation in (15): (15) High applicatives Luganda a. Katonga ya- kwant- i-dde K Past-hold- APPL-PAST ‘Katonga held the bag for Mukasa.’ Mukasa M Chaga b. n-a-y-lyi-`a m-k`a k-elya. Foc-1sg-PRES-eat-APL-FV 1-wife 7-food ‘He is eating food for his wife.’ (Bresnan & Moshi 1993:49-50) ensawo. bag (Pylkkanen 2002: 25) 25 c. VoiceP DPNOM Ext.Arg. High Applicative Voice’ Voice vP v’ v0 ApplP DPDAT Applied Arg. Appl’ Appl0 VP V0 DPACC Theme Cuervo (2003) argues that psychological verb constructions may also be interpreted as high applicatives in which the high Appl0 head projects the dative experiencer argument, and the latter is interpreted as ‘a Benefactee’ of an event: (16) A Daniela Daniela.dative ‘Daniela likes cats.’ ApplP le CL.DAT gustan los like.PL the gatos. cats Appl’ DPDAT A Daniela Appl0 vPBE Le DP v’ Los gatos vBE V0 gust (Cuervo 2003: 31) The nominative theme (los gatos ‘cats’) is the subject of the stative predicate gustar ‘like’, while the Experiencer is external to the vP. The latter argument is argued to be licensed by the high Appl0 head. 26 Notice that the number of arguments involved in applicative relations (high and low) is essentially the same, but there is a semantic difference between them, which can be attributed to the participation of an event argument. In high applicatives, this event argument enters into a relation with the applied one, while in low applicatives, two DP arguments, the applied and the theme are in close-knit relation with each other. As mentioned above, the applied argument must be a recipient, source, or stative possessor of the theme. By contrast, in high applicatives of psychological predicates shown in (16), the argument structure contains one less phrasal argument since only the experiencer and the theme arguments are projected, and not the external argument. In such structures, the experiencer does not enter in any above-mentioned relations of low-applicatives. Chapter 3 addresses the question of whether there is an overt morphological realization of these relationships in Georgian and related languages. 1.3 Variation of causatives and applicatives in terms of complement type Besides the voice bundling parameter, causatives can also vary in the type of complement that CAUSE takes (Pylkkänen 2002). Pylkkänen identifies three kinds of complement that CAUSE may take: root, VP, and vP. Root-selecting CAUSE results in a lexical causative, which may have idiosyncratic meaning and is unproductive relative to syntactic causatives in a language like Japanese (Harley 2008). The VP and the vPselecting causative heads usually form a syntactic causative, which has non-idiosyncratic meaning and is highly productive across various classes of verbs. The causative heads that select the vP will be referred to as phase-selecting causatives following Chomsky 27 (1999, 2001), McGinnis (2000, 2001a, b), and Arad (2003, 2004) among others. Here are the illustrations of these structures: (17)a. ROOT-selecting CAUSE ROOT CAUSE b. Verb-selecting CAUSE CAUSE ROOT v d. Phase-selecting CAUSE CAUSE vP v VP … The complement type of CAUSE has further consequences for the event composition in a sentence. Root-selecting CAUSE behaves like a mono-eventive structure with respect to the scope of adverbial because there is only one place in the clause where the adverbial can attach: only VP can be modified in the root-selecting (lexical) causative. The same prediction can be true for VP-selecting causatives. In the following English causative of an inchoative verb, the manner adverbial reluctantly is expected to modify 28 both the causing and the resulting events regardless of whether it attaches to a position higher or lower than the VP itself: (18) VP-modifying adverbial: a. Bill opened the door reluctantly. b. Bill reluctantly opened the door. (Compare: The door opened reluctantly.) In these sentences, the adverbial can not modify the causing and the resulting events separately since zero-derived causatives of inchoatives in English do not allow such separate modification of events: they are lexical causatives. Bi-eventive interpretations are found with vP-selecting causatives (i.e. causatives in which CAUSE takes phasecomplete vPs as its complement). Adverbials can modify both the causing and the resulting events individually depending on the attachment site (above or lower than vP). Pylkkänen claims that vP-selecting causatives contain two vPs: the head of the first vP expresses the causing event, and the head of the second vP, the resulting event. Therefore, each of these events can be modified: (19) The causing event modified a. Sue reluctantly made John eat oysters. b. Sue made John eat oysters reluctantly. In (19a), reluctantly modifies the causing event and is interpreted as oriented toward the external causer argument Sue, while in (19b), the same manner adverbial modifies the resulting eating event, i.e., is oriented towards John. Thus, the adverbial test indicates bieventive properties of vP-selecting causatives. We will also use the test of depictive modification as a diagnostic of mono- and bi-eventive properties of different types of causatives. As is illustrated throughout Chapter 2, a depictive modifier can modify the causee argument of the syntactic causative which matches its case marking with the 29 depictive while it is impossible to modify the causer argument from the same position even when the case marking is matched with the relevant argument. The idea is that the modification of the causer and the causee in syntactic causatives must be local and presumably, these two arguments are projected in separate ‘clauses’. Therefore, the event structure of syntactic causatives is more complex than that of the lexical one. Applicatives also allow us to probe the mono- or bi-eventive properties of the complements selected by the Appl0 head. High and low applicatives show a distinction in terms of mono-/bi-eventiveness. Recall that in low applicatives, the low Appl0 head does not take a verbal complement because it merges below VP licensing the theme and the applied arguments as in (13)-(14). Since in these structures, the low Appl0 head does not take a phase-complete complement, they are not subject to the same bi-eventive analysis as vP-selecting syntactic causatives. Adverbials in low applicatives are expected to modify higher verbal projections, such as vP and VP, and the structure is interpreted as mono-eventive. For instance, in (20), the manner adverbial again modifies the baking event: (20) Adverbial modification of low applicative Sheila baked John a cake again. Returning to high-applicatives, the Appl0 head that merges above VP does not introduce a separate event into the semantics of complex predicates, i.e. it does not select for vP complement as illustrated in (17c) for vP-selecting causatives. 4 Cross- 4 Here we follow Pylkkanen (2002) and McGinnis (2002, 2004) in which it is proposed that the high applicative relation is established between an individual and an event due to the Appl0 head selecting for the VP complement. See the tree in (15c) for details. 30 linguistically, vP is argued to introduce an event argument (Harley 1995, Pylkkanen 2002, Cuervo 2003 among others). One might argue that the event structure of high applicatives cannot be as complex as that of vP-selecting syntactic causatives where two events are introduced: the causing and the resulting one (i.e. two separate vPs). Since the event structure of a high applicative is simpler than that of the vP-selecting causative, the manner adverbial is expected to modify just the VP complement of the Appl0 head and show the properties of mono-eventive structures: (21) Modification of VP-high applicative in Georgian a. gia-s avaria moulodnelad Gia-dative accident unexpectedly ‘The accident happened to Gia unexpectedly.’ b. mo- uxda prev- APPLIC- happen gia-s avaria mo- uxda Gia-dative accident prev- APPLIC- happened ‘The accident happened to Gia unexpectedly.’ moulodnelad. unexpectedly In these examples, the interpretation of the scope of an adverbial can be the one where unexpectedly modifies the event described by the verb. Both in (21a) and (21b), the scope of the adverbial is the same since it modifies the same event of happening. A detailed explanation of high applicative semantics with the verbs of happening will be given in Section 3.8 of Chapter 3. The simpler event structure of high and low applicatives and the size of the complement that both Appl0 heads take means that the resulting structure will always show mono-eventive properties with respect to adverbial scope. 1.4 Theoretical framework 1.4.0 Distributed Morphology (DM) 31 This work utilizes the framework of Distributed Morphology (DM) in the analysis of the morphosyntax of complex predicates in South Caucasian languages. In this framework (Halle & Marantz 1993, henceforth H&M), word and sentence formation are viewed as a product of single derivational mechanism, and the morphology itself is distributed among several components of the grammar. Word formation may happen at any level where the head movement and merger of structurally adjacent heads create complex heads (H&M 1993: 112). In DM, the terminal nodes in syntax from which words are formed do not have any phonological features, and the nodes obtain those features only at the level of Morphological Structure (MS) by the process called Vocabulary Insertion. Vocabulary Items (henceforth, VIs) can be underspecified. For example, the Vocabulary entry for the English verb sink is sufficiently underspecified so that it can be inserted in either inchoative or causative contexts (Harley & Noyer 2000). For vocabulary insertion to happen, it is enough that the feature bundle of the Vocabulary Item (VI) does not conflict with the features of the terminal (H & M, 1993:121). It may be that several VIs compete for the insertion in the same terminal node at the MS. The VI that matches the most features of the node will be inserted 5. The architecture of the grammar in DM is shown in (22): 5 Known as the ‘subset principle’ (H & M1993). 32 (22) (Harley & Noyer 1997:3) Morphosyntactic features [Det] [1st] [CAUSE] [+pst] [root] [pl] etc. Syntactic operations Merge, Move, Copy Morphological operations Logical Form (LF) Phonological Form (PF) (Insertion of Vocabulary Items, Readjustment, phonological rules) Vocabulary Items [kæt]:root], [+count], Conceptual Interface [+animate], etc. Encyclopedia (Non-linguistics knowledge) Cat: four legs, feline, pet, purrs, scratches; In this model, it is assumed that roots are underived primitives in syntactic derivations, i.e. they are ‘atomic’ non-compositional items. The syntax manipulates just placeholders or roots, and these abstract elements receive phonological content when vocabulary insertion applies. Syntactic category in this system is derived from syntactic position. Roots are lexical elements underspecified for lexical category (Arad 2003, 2005, Marantz 1997, 2000, 33 Embick 1998). They are marked with the symbol and are combined with the categorydefining head (such as a adjectival, n nominal head, etc.). It is of importance to note that according to DM model (Halle & Marantz 1993), the ordering of constituents within words and the ordering of words within sentences do not obey the same principles, such as ‘head’, ‘specifier, or ‘complement’ configurations of syntactic building blocks, which trigger a certain ordering of affixes with respect to stems and of phrases to syntactic heads. Consequently, different ordering of root/stems with respect to affixes in various languages has little to do with the merging position of these elements in syntax. The fact that in Georgian and related languages, the roots are located in the fourth position of the verbal template followed by 4-5 affixes, and in Navajo, roots come at the end of the template preceded by about 9 affixes are arbitrary and an affix’s status as a prefix, suffix, or infix is independent of its syntactic role, although in the default situation we do expect that the hierarchical morphological structure will mirror a syntactic hierarchy from which it is derived as per the ‘Mirror Principle’ (Baker 1988) . This idea will be expanded in Section 1.5 where the status of templates in the theory of grammar is discussed. One of the issues dealt within this study is the linearization of the morphemes in a well-formed phonological word at morphological structure level (MS). As many argue (Halle & Marantz 1993, Noyer 1997, Embick 2003, 2008 among others), linearization is a property of phonological structure and in no way X0s get linearized in syntax. Further, Noyer (1997) argues that “linearization applies in the first phase of Morphological Structure, supplying adjacency relations to all constituents...” (Noyer 1997:38). He 34 claims that at MS two demands determine the mapping of the functional heads and their morphosyntactic representations to phonological strings: (1) morphological wellformedness conditions on morphological words, and (2) two types of rules: readjustment rules, which change just the phonological material and second, rules, which supply phonological material (affixes) to stems, essentially discharging the features of morphosyntactic representations. Some of these rules will appear instrumental for understanding the morpheme ordering in complex words in this dissertation. Thus, DM recognizes that at MS morphemes may be inserted to meet universal and/or language-specific well-formedness conditions (Halle and Marantz 1993:115). An example of such addition is when subject-verb agreement is implemented by adjoining an Agr morpheme to the Tns node and then the features of the subject are copied onto the Agr node. Such addition of terminal nodes at MS changes the number of terminal elements that might find phonological realization and naturally, disrupt the isomorphism between PF and syntax. Other processes that may disturb such a one-to-one relation between terminal nodes in syntax and the elements at MS are: head-to-head movement of a terminal element and adjunction to a terminal element in the tree; merger of structurally adjacent nodes but keeping their identities-fusion, fission or impoverishment of certain features at MS before the Vocabulary Insertion. For discussion on the exact nature of these processes I will refer the reader to Halle and Marantz (1993). A detailed explanation of the processes relevant to the analysis of the data in this study is provided where relevant. 35 1.4.1 Chomsky’s (1999, 2001) notion of phases The dissertation assumes the most recent version of the Minimalist Program as argued in Chomsky (1999, 2001). In these versions of the program, the derivation of syntactic expressions proceeds cyclically, phase by phase. Chomsky identifies two phrases as being ‘strong’: vP and CP -- the verbal and the complementizer phrases which have a ‘propositional’ structure. The ‘strong’ phases are spelled out cyclically. The cyclicity of syntactic derivations and spellout has natural implications for the derivations of words. One goal of the research here is to explore to what extent the strong phases of syntactic derivations (vP and CP) can be the sites of cyclic spellout, and more importantly, whether the functional heads introducing non-core arguments to the argument structure of causatives and applicatives can also head a phase. In particular, we will be looking at the status of causative and applicative heads. The key evidence for the cyclicity of these heads is supplied by the presence of contextual allomorphy in the morphemes inserted into these heads (Embick 2009). The next section overviews Embick’s findings in this respect. 1.4.2 Contextual allomorphy as evidence for phasehood (Embick 2009) Embick (2009) claims that morphological operations-- which determine the phonological form of morphemes — are constrained by the cyclic organization of the grammar, i.e. by the local domains that are defined by syntax. He develops a localist theory of allomorphy, in which linear adjacency and cyclic locality interact to produce a theory of allomorphic interaction. Take, for example, contextually-defined allomorphy, illustrated in (23) for English past tense suffixes. We can view this as the result of 36 Vocabulary Insertion assigning a phonological form to the morphemes computed in syntax. VIs (Vocabulary Items) compete for insertion into a given node. The most specific item, matching the node’s featural content, gives that node its phonological structure: (23) VIs for the English Past tense -t TPAST / ____ {LEAVE, BEND,…} - TPAST / ____ {HIT, SING, …} 6 -d TPAST (Embick 2009: 9) As seen from these items, Roots like BEND and HIT ‘condition’ the insertion of –t and - allomorphs. –d is a default elsewhere item for the [Past] and is only inserted when the context for other morphemes is not defined. The cyclic domains of syntactic computations may render the insertion of certain VIs possible as opposed to other VIs. For example, the idea that roots are acategorial elements and that they merge with the category-defining functional heads such as a, n is well-supported (Arad (2000), (2003), Marantz (1997), (2000) among others)). When these category-defining heads merge with roots, they are root-attached, i.e. they are in the inner domain. The same categorydefining head may be attached to a structure that has already been categorized by another head. In such instances, the head which merges later is argued to be an outer domain head. Embick & Marantz (2008) argue that both inner and outer domain heads that categorize roots are cyclic, which means that when merged into a structure, they trigger spellout, the operation that sends the part of the syntactic structure to the interface 6 We may argue that SING is a zero-derived past form much like as HIT since it does not change the affix in the PAST, but rather the Root. 37 components, PF and LF. Observe these inner and outer domain category-defining heads in the examples adapted from Embick (2009): (24) v merged with ROOT (25) Two category-defining heads and ROOT root v a -able v BREAK In (24), the single category-defining head v merges with the root first defines a phase. In (25), we have two domains because there are two category defining heads (a and v). An important property of outer heads like a in (25) is that vocabulary insertion into this position is not root-conditioned. By contrast, non-cyclic heads (like T0 in (26)) in the outer domain allow contextually-defined allomorphy. For example, English past tense suffixes –t/- still show the above-noted root-conditioned allomorphy even though the tense morpheme is not root-attached, and it is in outer domain as seen in (26). It is argued that the root first merges with the category-defining v and that T0 is introduced later in the derivation: (26) English Past tense T T [PAST] -t/- v ROOT v (Embick 2009:10) T0 is not a cyclic head as argued in Chomsky (1999, 2001) since it is not phonologically independent and does not have a ‘propositional’ structure. The cyclic v does not block T0 from showing contextual allomorphy conditioned by roots. Therefore, 38 Embick posits that there is a critical need to accommodate cases where the functional heads attach higher than the cyclic category-defining heads yet still show root-determined allomorphy. Another problem relates to the contextual allomorphy displayed by the nominalizer category-defining head in English gerunds like John’s marrying of Kathy. In gerunds, the nominalizer n morpheme spelled out as –ing attaches to the structure already verbalized by v: (27) Gerund derivation n [n, -ing] v MARRY [v, -] (Embick 2009:11) The VI –ing inserted into the outer cyclic head n shows no root-determined allomorphy, although on the surface one might think that it is attached to the root. Embick concludes that there are evidently no cases in which an Outer cyclic head shows Root-determined allomorphy as opposed to non-cyclic ones. Based on this evidence, he develops two theoretical generalizations that capture the allomorphic variation of the English past tense morphemes and the lack of this allomorphy with respect to the nominal category-defining heads (like –ing in (27)) in gerunds. Here are these generalizations: (28) “a. …. ] x] Z ] Generalization 1: Non-cyclic Z may show contextual allomorphy determined by , as long as x is not overt. b….] x] y] Generalization 2: Cyclic y may not show contextual allomorphy determined by , even if x is not overt.” (Embick 2009: 11) 39 The idea behind these sequences of functional heads in (28a & b) is that outer noncyclic heads can see across an Inner cyclic node, but outer cyclic heads cannot. In (28), lower case x, y are cyclic heads, upper-case Z is non-cyclic head, and is an allomorphyconditioning element, i.e. Root. Thus, in (28a), non-cyclic Z may be influenced by , if the intervening head x is not phonologically realized. However, cyclic y may not be influenced by , because y will trigger the spellout of the structure assembled by the point when y merges. Thus, the phonological realization of x is irrelevant for the contextual allomorphy of the outer cyclic head y. Another conclusion drawn from Embick (2009) is that contextual allomorphy is possible only with elements that are concatenated. However, in some cases, superficially adjacent elements cannot influence each other allomorphically because they are not active in the same PF cycle and are separated by a ‘strong’ phase (such as vP or CP as argued in Chomsky (1999)). In the former case, the conclusion is straightforward: only those morphemes that are adjacent can influence each other, while, in the latter case, superficially adjacent elements may be separated by zero-realized cyclic heads that may render the contextual allomorphy of the outer cyclic head impossible. These conclusions will be taken into consideration when examining the data of causative and applicative predicates in this work. 1.4.3 Kratzer (1994) on the VoiceP and external arguments 40 Since Kratzer (1994, 1996), it has been generally assumed that an external argument is not a ‘true’ arguments of a verb, but is rather introduced by an inflectional head outside of the VP shell (such as vP). Using some of the Neo-Davidsonian argument association methods, she argues that external arguments have different semantics due to the way they are introduced in the syntax of verbs. She specifically argues that the external argument is introduced to the syntax by the separate functional projection such as VoiceP and they are different from internal object arguments in that they never impose specific interpretations on verbs as internal arguments do. The relevant evidence came from Marantz (1984) in which the external argument was shown not to form idioms with V0 in contrast to the arguments projected by VP itself as shown in the following: (29) Idioms of English a. throw support behind the candidate b. throw a party c. throw a fit (Marantz 1984 quoted from Kratzer 1994:113). In these structures, while an internal argument may trigger a certain interpretation of the verb, the external argument fails to do so. Following Marantz, Kratzer concludes that the external argument is not a ‘true’ argument of the verb and develops this idea into a coherent theory of VoiceP according to which the external argument is the argument of Voice0 while the internal one is the argument of VP, specifically, the latter is generated in the specifier of the VP as illustrated in the following: 41 (30) Mittie fed the dog. VoiceP DP Mittie Voice’ Voice Agent VP DP V’ the dog V {feed} (Kratzer 1994:121) Furthermore, the internal argument in (29) and (30) first composes with the verb enabling it to impose certain interpretations on the resulting expression, while the agent argument composes with a separate light verb (or Voice) and then is conjoined with the lower predicate via a process called Event Identification (EI). This process is basically the conjunction operation applied to the separate functions followed by co-indexing of the event variables. Co-indexing happens due to the shared <s, t> type functions in the input functions as seen in (31). As the result of EI, the denotation of type <e, <s, t>> , which includes Voice with the external argument, composes with the denotation of the type <s, t> (including VP with internal argument) to produce a function of the type <e, <s, t>> which is Voice’ 7 : (31) a. EVENT IDENTIFICATION (EI) <e, <s, t>> Input1 7 <s, t> ⇒ input2 <e, <s, t>> output The following entities denote individuals (e), events (s) and truth values (t). 42 b. Brutus stabbed Caesar. VoiceP x.e. [stabbing(e) & Agent (e, Brutus) & theme (e, Caesar] Voice’ x.e. [stabbing(e) & Agent (e, x) & theme (e, Caesar) Brutus (By event identification) VoiceAGENT x.e. [Agent (e, x)] e.[stabbing (e) & theme (e, Caesar) Stab Caesar x.e. [stabbing(e) & theme(e, Caesar) (Pylkkanen 2002: 13) In the computation of the denotation of complex events the EI allows the same existential operator to bind into the two event arguments. This kind of EI is assumed to exist in causative and applicative constructions in this dissertation where Voice head also introduces an event variable and the external argument to the event structure of these predicates. Thus, the compositionality of the external argument with the VP is expected due to this process. 1.4.4 Cuervo (2003) on different flavors of little vs Cuervo (2003) posits three types of heads that may either themselves be the complements of various functional heads (such as the ApplHIGH ), or take the Appl0LOW as their complement: (32) Three types of heads a. Event-introducers: little v0s. b. Argument introducers: Voice0 and Appl0 c. Roots These three heads may introduce arguments in the syntax by the combination of the lexical Root and the verbalizing head (little v). Roots combine with different kinds of 43 little v (Marantz 1991, Harley 1995) to build event predicates, which have different meanings depending on the type or the ‘flavor’ of these little vs. Based on event structure research, this work acknowledges that arguments are licensed either by an event predicate or by an argument-introducing head (Voice0 or Appl0). Roots may also introduce arguments semantically as their complements (Levin 1999, Kratzer 1996). In this work, I will argue that these little v0 heads may also introduce arguments to the structure of causative and other constructions. Specifically, they add causee arguments to the structure of make X do V syntactic causatives. Given these assumptions about how the argument structure is composed in the syntax, Cuervo identifies the following types of little vs that define the meaning of predicates: (33) Three types of v a. vDO b. vGO c. vBE Three types of events example activities dance, run changes fall, go, die states like, admire In this typology of event heads, vDO and vGO introduce dynamic events while vBE introduces stative eventualities (Bach 1986), which are mainly represented by psychological predicates and verbs like lie, hold, etc. Usually vDO heads active structures and combines with Voice0, which introduces an external argument (Kratzer 1994). It can be assumed that various activity verbs, both transitive and intransitive (unergatives), are formed with this vDO. Predicates of change are derived with vGO and include the verbs of movement and happening. This kind of event does not license an external argument via the Voice0 head. 44 These are mainly change-of-state verbs, which include events denoting non-volitional changes and they select for an object DP undergoing the change-of-state (ex. fall and die). Thus, when vGO combines with roots of unaccusatives, this typically results in a change-of-state interpretation for the theme argument. In contrast to the two dynamic vs, vBE combines with Roots to express states and Roots combining with this head license dative subject DPs in the specifier of VP (verbs like matter and Spanish be useful). Stative psychological predicates are formed by this kind of vBE. Given these three main types of v, the syntactic composition of complex events such as causatives, inchoatives, and applicatives is accounted for. I follow Cuervo’s taxonomy of little v heads in chapters both on causatives and applicatives for simple events but crucially, her decomposition of the causative head (CAUSE) into two different types of v (vDO and vBE ) will not be accepted for the purposes of presentation in this chapter. 1.5 Status of templates and assumptions about the morphosyntax of Georgian and related languages This section overviews some of the basic grammatical features of Georgian and related languages based on the existing literature on these languages and the writer’s own observations as a native speaker. Most of the data and functional analyses of morphemes are drawn from Howard Aronson’s (1990) Georgian: A reader’s grammar, O. Kajaia’s (2004) Mingrelian-Georgian Dictionary and V. Topuria’s monograph (1967) Svan Language. 45 All three languages are moderately polysynthetic. The number of lexical and functional morphemes marked on verbs can grow to up to 10-12 morphemes per word, but is more typically 5-6. There is a great deal of fusion among different inflectional morphemes such as between person and number agreement, series, screeve, 8 or mood markers, etc. on both sides of stems, i.e. in the pre- and post-base positions. However, fusion does not usually affect the argument structure-changing morphemes, which mark syntactic alternations such as causative, applicative, etc. The section extends the discussion on the structure of the Georgian verbal template along with the language-specific restrictions on the realization of certain morphology in the pre- and post-base positions. The status of verbal templates in the linguistic theory is also discussed in light of DM and Baker’s Mirror Principle (1985) highlighting the fact that the latter principle is often a default situation in the grammar and that templatic constraints are essentially language-specific well-formedness rules as argued in Noyer (1997). 1.5.0 The structure of the verbal template According to Aronson (1990), the Georgian verb template contains a maximum of three positions for morphemes before the root and as many as 6-8 positions after the root. Observe the following scheme of the Georgian verb: 8 Series and screeves are the terms drawn from the Kartvelian (South Caucasian) linguistics that stand for the conjugation pattern of verbs in terms of tense, aspect and mood (TAM). There are three series in Georgian and Svan, and four in Mingrelian. The screeve is a conjugation pattern for just one value of tense, aspect and mood. 46 Table 1. The morphological template of the Georgian verb 1 2 Preverb Person agreement (subject, object 3 Applicative, Causative, Voice, etc. 4 Root 5 Theme 6 Causative, Passive, etc. 7 Screeve 8 Theme 9 Causative (screeve) 10 Person agreement/ Series Before explaining the distribution of these various morphemes in the template, note that the status of a morpheme in this kind of template, i.e. whether it is a prefix, infix or suffix, has no direct relation with the syntactic operations combining terminal nodes to create words before the Vocabulary Insertion. In DM, the hierarchical location of affixes in words is determined by the syntax but again there need not be a direct one-to-one relation between the terminal elements in syntax and phonological exponents, neither need the bracketing of the phonological pieces directly reflect the syntactic bracketing (H & M 1993:11). As H & M show in this foundational article on DM, Baker’s Mirror Principle arguing for the transparent relation between the checking of features in the syntax and the ordering affixes in a word as a result of this checking is not consistently accurate. In other words, the order of checked features does not always reflect the order of affixation in the lexicon whereby the features of the innermost affix are checked first and the subsequent features are reflected in word formation based on their order of 47 checking in the syntax. H & M reject this principle as too restrictive because natural languages provide plentiful evidence against such a strict correspondence between the checking of features on terminal nodes and their phonological realization in their mapping to the Phonological Form (PF). Given this sometimes arbitrary relation between the syntax of complex expressions and their phonological realization at PF one might argue that the structure of the verbal template in a particular language(s) is purely epiphenomenal and has little to do with syntactic derivations. Therefore, the order of affixes with respect to Root and the position of the Root with respect to these morphemes may be considered as the result of language-specific constraints on the morphological well-formedness rather than the direct consequence of the order in which the checking of these features proceeds. Thus, the position of morphemes in the verbal or nominal templates need not be viewed as a direct consequence of their syntax. In the Georgian verb template shown in Table 3 the order of three pre-base morphemes is rigid, which means that in relevant syntactic contexts where all three morphemes are realized, the ordering is the same: first preverbal prefixes are realized followed by the person agreement markers, and finally, argument-structure changing morphemes such as causative, applicative, voice, etc. The causative, applicative, or Voice functional heads have multiple phonological exponents whose insertion depends on the syntactic environment and the feature content on these nodes. Again the ordering of these morphemes in the template above may have nothing to do with the order of checking of relevant features in the syntax. 48 The preverbal prefixes mark both aspect and directionality and as such, they combine the features of both inflectional and derivational morphology. These elements resemble Russian preverbs, which, along with the perfective-imperfective distinction can mark manner, saturation, or the intensity of an event expressed by the verb. In the latter function, these preverbal elements are like the derivational morphology in that they imbue a special meaning to the root, and are not productive. There are fifteen such preverbal prefixes in Georgian and they are inserted into the initial slot of the template, although we assume that the functional head which is realized with these prefixal elements (which presumably is Asp0) does not check its features the latest assuming a bottom-up derivation of words in the syntax. The person agreement prefixes are spelled out in the second and the final positions of the verbal template. A separate section below discusses which arguments trigger insertion of these morphemes along with the case-marking of relevant DPs. Only one personnumber agreement morpheme appears in the pre-base position even when the verb is transitive and contains two arguments. The reason for such restricted spellout of the agreement morphemes will be explained below. The third position, which immediately precedes the base (root) can be occupied by various morphemes marking the argument structure of relevant verbs, including causative, applicative, and voice morphemes. The VIs of one of these functional heads are in competition for insertion in this position. Various post-syntactic rules are also implicated in the spellout of these morphemes, to be discussed in Chapters 2-3 where relevant. 49 The order of morphemes in the post-base positions of the Georgian verb template is not as rigid as in the pre-base environment, and some of the morphemes tend to reiterate sometimes for no obvious semantic reason. The morphemes that can be repeated are the thematic markers (especially one of the five suffixes –eb) and the syntactic causative morpheme marking the make X do V causative alternation (-in). The iterated markers do not usually contribute the same semantics twice, as in the case of reduplicated causative suffix: the second –in does not introduce another causing event or causee argument to the argument structure. Instead, the reduplicated causative morpheme may mark the series/screeve or mood information as shown in the following Perfective series forms: (34) The Perfective series verb ga- m- eket- ebinebinoprev-1S-Voice- make- TH- CAUS- TH- CAUS- TAM‘I would have caused X to make Y.’ s 3O To the best of my knowledge the exact function of this iterated causative marker has not been explained in traditional linguistic literature on Georgian and I provisionally gloss this morpheme as the conjunctive perfect (screeve) marker. Thematic markers glossed as TH in this dissertation are widely attested in the morphology of various verbal and nominal classes cross-linguistically and they are morphological well-formedness affixes not associated with any specific terminal node in the syntax. As argued by Halle & Embick (2003), among others, they are dummy elements and do not realize any particular functional head. In addition, I argue that they ‘signal’ the presence of certain functional morphology in individual languages. In Georgian and related languages, the thematic marker (-eb) has been argued to indicate the 50 presence of the causative morpheme (Aronson 1990), although this relation is not always clear. This will be illustrated in Chapter 2. Among other morphemes inserted into various post-base positions, the morphemes marking causative, voice, agreement, and case are the most important for understanding further discussion in this work. The causative morpheme –in marks the causative head added to unaccusative, transitive, or other classes of verbs. The morpheme marking the passive alternation also shows up in the same post-base position in relevant syntactic contexts. Finally, the person-number agreement morphemes inserted in the final position may be fused with the series markers or be absent entirely. 1.5.1 Assumptions about language-specific templatic constraints An essential note on Georgian verbal morphology is concerned with language-specific constraints on the spellout of certain morphemes in the verbal template. Such constraints limit the positions-of-exponence for the phonological pieces inserted into terminal nodes. For example, only one person agreement morpheme can be inserted in the pre-base position, as well as one argument structure-changing morpheme. I suggest that this type of restriction is similar to the templatic structure discussed by Noyer (1997) in the Arabic verb paradigm and in other Afro-Asiatic languages, whereby a single terminal node is associated with two positions-of-exponence. This situation can result in ‘discontinuous bleeding,’ in which the morpheme inserted in one position-of-exponence bleeds the insertion of another morpheme in another position-of-exponence. Following Noyer, I assume that in Georgian and related languages, the phi- and other substantive morphosynatctic features are subject to arbitrarily-imposed constraints on the verbal 51 template. One such constraint limits the insertion of person features of a subject or an object into the second and the final positions as shown in the following scheme: (35) Restriction on person agreement morphemes: …. 2 base (root) final person agreement person/number agreement (subject, object…) (subject, object…) There is only one terminal node and two positions-of-exponence for the person/number features of a subject and/or object even when both arguments are referentially marked, i.e. represent 1-2 person and present in a sentence. Note that only the features of referentially marked arguments (1-2 person, i.e. [+participant] or [+PSE 9])) are realized in the mentioned positions. A separate post-base position of person agreement morphemes also allows the spellout of the person features of 3rd person arguments. The morphemes realizing these arguments are usually fused with the series markers. A similar constraint is operative with respect to argument structure-marking morphemes such as causative, applicative, voice, etc. illustrated with the following scheme: base/root 6 3 Causative, Causative, Passive, etc Voice, Applicative, etc. (36) …. The numbers indicate the positions of these morphemes in the verbal template. Thus, one position is available for the causative, applicative, and voice markers in different 9 This feature is posited in Halle (1997) for designating the Participants of Speech Events, i.e. the referential arguments. 52 syntactic contexts. It is often the case that the Voice marker bleeds the causative or the applicative marker in various syntactic contexts or vice versa. The relevant empirical evidence and its analysis will be provided in the chapters dealing with these constructions. The restricted spellout of these morphemes may be a part of general economy strategies on the spellout of substantive morphosyntactic features. Summing up this section, the following points should be taken into account when analyzing the morphosyntax of causatives and applicatives: The structure of the verbal template in Georgian may include a maximum of 10-12 morphemes, which are asymmetrically linearized in the pre- and post-base positions: no more than three morphemes can occur in the pre-base position, while the number of morphemes in the post-base position is highly variable reaching a maximum of 6-8 morphemes. The morphological realization of various morphemes is subject to arbitrarily imposed restrictions that make only limited positions-of-exponence available for certain morphemes. We assume that mismatches between syntax-semantics and the morphology of complex expressions are due to not only various restrictions on the spellout of morphemes but also to the readjustment rules operative in the post-syntactic component. With these observations as background, the next section overviews phi- and case feature checking in syntax. 1.6 Case and agreement with various classes of verbs The three languages of the South Caucasian language family display aspectuallyconditioned split ergativity instantiated by variation between nominative, ergative, and dative cases on subjects, and dative/accusative/nominative/absolutive cases on objects, 53 across three series of transitive, and unergative classes of verbs. There are three such series in Georgian: the Present, the Aorist, and the Perfective. The three series consist of 11 screeves. The screeves represent the conjugation pattern for one specific combination of Tense, Aspect, and Mood. The three series differentially mark the case of subjects and objects. In particular, the subjects of transitive and unergative verbs are assigned different cases in the different series: nominative in the Present, ergative in the Aorist, and dative in the Perfective. The following tables show the screeves in the three series and the corresponding case marking of the arguments of transitive and unergative verbs: Table 2. The structure of the series in Georgian Series Present (S=Nom) Aorist (S=Erg) Perfective (S=Dative) (Present group) (Future group) Screeves present imperfect conjunctive present future conditional conjunctive future pluperfect conjunctive past conjunctive perfect aorist present perfect (evidential) Table 3. Case marking of transitive verb arguments External argument Theme Goal/Beneficiary Present series Nom Dative [Dative] 10 Aorist series Erg. Acc [Dative] Perfective series Dative Nom [Gen-PP] Note that the case marking of the subjects of unergative verbs is the same as that for transitives, but objects are not projected in unergative structures. The examples in (37) illustrate the case marking of subjects and objects in double object constructions (DOCs) across the various series: 10 The brackets indicate the optionality of the projection of the Goal/Beneficiary argument in transitive structures. However, the external and the theme/patient arguments are mandatory as indicated with the absence of these brackets. 54 (37)a. Present series (active): Nodar-i bavshv-s t'k'bileul-s Nodar-Nom child-Dat candy-Acc ‘Nodar is presenting a candy to the child.’ chuknis. presents.Pres b. Aorist Series (active): Nodar-ma bavshv-s t'k'bileu-i Nodar-Erg child-Dat candy-Abs ‘Nodar presented a candy to the child.’ achuka. presented.Aor c. Perfective Series (active, irrealis): Nodar-s bavshv-is-tvis t'k'bileul-i uchukebia. Nodar-Dat child-Gen-for candy-Abs presented.Perf. ‘Nodar has (apparently) presented the candy to the child.’ Notice that in the Perfective series, the subject is assigned the dative case and the benefactee object receives a postpositional genitive, which indicates the latter’s nonargumental position, as this argument no longer triggers the agreement with the verb (I assume that this argument is in an adjunct position). Due to such differential case marking of the subject, two agreement patterns emerge in Georgian. Nominative and ergative subjects trigger basic agreement (Aronson 1990), which is realized with the ‘vset’ markers, while object agreement is realized with ‘m-set’ affixes. The terms ‘v-set’ and ‘m-set’ are based on the first person agreement markers of subjects and objects in transitive contexts. These sets are shown in Table 6 that follows. V-set and m-set agreement affixes cannot show up simultaneously in the same verb because of the abovementioned templatic restrictions 11. 11 I will refer a reader to Lomashvili & Harley (in press) for detailed explanation of the role of templates in spellout of agreement morphology in Georgian. 55 When subjects of transitive and unergative verbs are assigned dative case, accusative shows up on the theme argument 12. The agreement pattern with the dative subjects is Inverse as it is realized by the ‘m-set’ agreement markers indexing subjects and ‘v-set’ affixes indexing Nom/Acc objects. The following table summarizes the ‘v-set’ and ‘mset’ affixes: Table 4. Georgian agreement morphology Per 1st 2 3 1 2 3 Num sg pl v-set markers v-/x-s, -a, -o v- -t m-set markers mg-, h-, sgv- -/x-t -en, -an, -nen, -n, -es g- -t -, h-, s- -t Both ‘m-set’ and ‘v-set’ paradigms are realized as prefixes when indexing the first and the second person arguments. The inverse pattern shows up in all syntactic contexts where subjects are assigned dative case. The relevant constructions, in addition to the Perfective series forms of transitive and unergative verbs, are subject-experiencer psychological predicates, two-place passives, adversity causatives, causatives of internally-changed verbs, and various applicatives, etc. Here are some examples: (38)a. The Present series: dato-s dzul-s dato-Dative hates.Pres ‘Dato hates Vano.’ Vano-. Vano-Nom b. The Aorist series: dato-s she- dzulda dato-Dat Prev- hated.Aor. ‘Dato hated Vano.’ 12 Vano- Vano-Nom Notice that Acc, Nom, and Absolutive have syncretic surface realizations in Georgian, i.e. they are marked with the morphological nominative marker. 56 c. The Perfective series: dato-s she- dzulebia dato-Dat Prev- hate.Perf. ‘Dato (apparently) hated Vano.’ Vano-. Vano-Nom In these examples, the third person dative subject triggers the ‘m-set’ agreement on verbs which is spelled out as zero. The first person nominative theme object of psychological verbs in (39) triggers ‘v-set’ agreement on verbs as illustrated in the following: (39) dato-s me dato-dat I-Nom ‘Dato missed me.’ mo- v- eprev- 1O- Voice- nat’re. miss However, when both dative and nominative arguments are 1-2 person, the agreement pattern is somewhat more complex, i.e. both subjects and objects trigger agreement on the morphologically complex verbs which consist of the main verb and the auxiliary BE. The main verb carries the meaning of the entire predicate, while the auxiliary ‘AR’ (BE) provides templatic extension for marking tense/aspect inflection along with the nominative object agreement on the predicate. Thus, the secondary function of auxiliary BE-support is to mark the agreement of nominative objects: (40) Inverse agreement (a) m- iq’var- x- ar 1- love- 2- BE 'I love you.sg' b) giq’var- v- ar 2love- 1- BE ‘You love me.’ In the inverse pattern, both simple and complex morphological forms of psychological verbs have the same argument structure, and the agreement morphology 57 seems to be sensitive to the markedness of one or both verbal arguments. 13 Other syntactic factors are also implicated in the spellout of subject and object person agreement in these complex forms, which I will not discuss here for space reasons. Note that tense/mood/aspect markers in these extended verbal units are kept intact, which again shows that they are not fused with the person/number agreement morphemes. Person agreement is not directly related to the main topic of this dissertation but it is important for the analysis of various types of causative and applicative predicates because of the way these constructions display variability in case marking of their main arguments. This information is also instrumental in understanding the interaction between the syntax-semantics and morphology of predicate constructions in this dissertation. 1.7 Outline of the Dissertation Both Chapters 2 and 3 begin with an overview of the existing research on causative and applicative constructions, and also discuss the same constructions in related languages (Mingrelian and Svan). The limited data available on these languages suggest that almost the same range of causative and applicative structures that are found in Georgian are available in these languages as well. Morphosyntactic properties of syntactic causatives derived from various classes of verbs (inchoative, unergative, unaccusative, etc.) are the focus of Chapter 2. Two main groups of syntactic causatives are identified: one taking inchoative verbs as an input to the causative alternation (melt/melt type alternations) and another, transitive, unergative, and other types of verbs resulting in make X do V alternations. Morphological distinctions 13 Markedrness of arguments in terms of person is defined whether these arguments are [+ participant] , i.e. 1-2 person, or [-participant], i.e. 3rd person. Marked arguments are usually [+participant]. 58 between these two main alternations are argued to arise from their syntactic structure and from the type of the complement that the causative head (CAUSE) takes in these types of causative structures. This chapter also contains a section on adversity and malefactive causatives, where the dative causee argument is the subject and no external argument is projected by the Voice0 head. I claim that these dative subjects form a natural class with the dative applied arguments of applicatives. The morphosyntactic and semantic properties of high and low applicatives are discussed in Chapter 3. First, I discuss low recipient and source applicatives of transitive and other classes of verbs where the transfer-of-possession relation is established between the external and applied arguments. This chapter also analyzes the stative possession relation in low applicatives formed with psychological and existential predicates. Two new types of applicatives are introduced in Chapter 3: those formed with 1) internally-caused change-of-state and 2) reflexive events. The applicative relation between the external argument and the theme in reflexive applicatives is argued to be established through the lower merging site of the reflexive Voice head, which ‘forces’ an empty argument PRO to occur in the specifier of the lower Appl0 head which also projects the accusative theme. The control relation between PRO and the external argument along with the low Appl0 head is argued to be responsible for the transfer-ofpossession relation between the external argument and the theme. Chapter 3 also discusses hybrid-type applicatives formed by four-place predicates in which high applicative relation is established between the higher applied argument and an event expressed by the verb, and low recipient relation is established between the applied 59 argument projected by the low Appl0 head and the theme. Some of these complex structures are argued also to combine CAUSE with the lower PHAVE/PLOC head which projects the Goal-Recipient and the theme arguments (Harley 2002, Jung & Miyagawa 2004) receiving either a ‘locative’ or ‘have’ interpretation. The study closes off with the discussion of applicative structures in Mingrelian and Svan, which appear to display the same range of applicative constructions as Georgian. Chapter 4 summarizes the basic findings of the study concerning the interface of the argument structure and the morphological realization of causative and applicative constructions. 60 CHAPTER 2 CAUSATIVE ALTERNATIONS IN GEORGIAN AND RELATED LANGUAGES 2.0 Introduction This chapter focuses on the causative alternation as it appears with various types of verbs (inchoative, unergative, transitive, psychological, etc.) in Georgian and the related languages Mingrelian and Svan. It specifically explores both lexical and syntactic causatives to identify the morphosyntactic properties of these constructions that are responsible for their productivity across various verb classes. The main goal of the chapter is to analyze the interaction between the argument structure of syntactic causatives and the morphological realization of the causative head. As in many morphologically rich languages, it is expected that there are mismatches between the syntax of these complex predicates and their morphological realization. These mismatches will be accounted for in the Distributed Morphology framework as indicated in the Introduction. 2.1 Organization and Outline of analysis In section 2.2, I outline my basic assumptions relevant to this chapter. In section 2.3, I discuss inchoative-causative alternations, which are morphologically realized with a-/ allomorphs. The novelty of the analysis presented in these sections is that the causative head selects RootP (P) as its complement in the causatives of inchoative verbs. This accounts for the relative productivity of the lexical causatives formed from inchoative alternates and the root-conditioned allomorphy of the causative head. In section 2.4, the morphosyntax of causatives formed from unergative verbs is discussed and the absence 61 of root-conditioned allomorphy of the causative head is accounted for by the size of the complement that it selects (that is, vP). It is argued that in a simple X makes Y do V causatives of unergative verbs such as sing, laugh ,etc. only one CAUSE is merged that takes the aforementioned vP complement. However, when the CAUSE iterates, two causing events are introduced into the structure and consequently, two causee arguments are introduced to the structure of these complex causatives. Consequently, the morphological realization of the two CAUSEs does reflect the syntax as two VIs (a- and –in) are inserted into separate CAUSE heads. In Section 2.5, I analyze the causatives of transitive verbs also as the result of a make X do V alternation and propose that in these structures, two causative heads are merged and the lower causative head selects for the argument-full vP complement. I propose that the presence and/or the lack of allomorphy of the causative head in the alternates of transitive/unergative verbs on the one hand and inchoatives on the other is a direct consequence of their syntax, namely, the size of the complement that the causative head takes. Beyond the analysis of the argument structure of various types of causatives, the iteration of causative morphemes and their complex syntax is discussed in various languages (Malagasy, Chemeheuvi, Georgian, Mingrelian and Svan). The conclusion regarding the iteration of causative morphemes is that the reduplicated Vocabulary Items (VIs) may not always mark the merger of two CAUSE heads in the same structure. Instead, one CAUSE morpheme marks the causative event head while another may mark some other functional head such as Aspect, Mood, or Tense. 62 Section 2.6 discusses the morphosyntax of adversity causatives whose syntax is argued to combine the Voice0 head with a [NonActive] feature and CAUSE head under one structure. The analysis of nonactive Voice in these structures is different from the previous literature (such as Kratzer 1994) in that it allows the Voice head not to project an external argument due to this [NonActive] feature. These structures project dative causee and nominative affected arguments none of them introduced by CAUSE head. In section 2.7, the event structure of ‘pretend-type’ complex verbal structures and their causatives is analyzed. These types of complex predicates have not yet been analyzed extensively in the literature. I propose that they combine a complex V0 head, including a lexical head turned into the grammaticalized functional head ‘PretendP’, and CAUSE composes with the vP and the VoiceP of a reflexive verb. Various event types of psychological predicates and their differences in terms of causativization represent the topic of section 2.8. Finally, in section 2.9, causative alternations of various types of verbs are analyzed in Mingrelian and Svan. 2.2 Assumptions Next, let us consider some basic assumptions and claims that have been made about the structure of causatives in other languages. We start with the distinction between socalled lexical causatives and syntactic causatives. We follow the approach espoused in Harley (2008) that both kinds of causative are formed in the syntax and differ only in the depth of embedding of the structure. After examining this, we turn to the hypothesis that causative morphology might be added at different ‘layers’ of the structure. 63 Harley (2008) (see also Miyagawa (1980), (1984), (1998), Jacobsen (1981), (1992) and Matsumoto (2000)) discusses two main classes of causatives in Japanese: lexical and syntactic causatives, seen in (4) and (5), where the syntactic causative has two different interpretations: (1) Lexical causative Taroo-ga zisyoku-o nio- ase-ta Taro-N resignation-A smell-ase-PST ‘Taro hinted at resignation.’ (Lit: ‘Taro made resignation smell’). (2) Syntactic (productive) causative a. Make-causative Hanako-wa Yoshi-o ik-ase-ta Hanako=T Youshi-A go-ase-PST ‘Hanako made Yoshi go.’ b. Let-causative Hanako-wa Yoshi-ni ik-ase-ta Hanako-T Yoshi-D go-ase-PST ‘Hanako allowed Yoshi to go/Hanako had Yoshi go.’ (Miyagawa (1980, 1984), Jacobsen (1981, 1992), Matsumoto (2000)). The differences between (1) and (2) are summarized in (3): (3) a. b. Lexical causatives monoclausal in terms of case-marking (only a single nominative case is possible on the Causer argument) can have idiomatic interpretation strong speaker sense of ‘listedness’, non-productivity, etc. Syntactic causatives biclausal by the tests involving scope, adverbial control, binding… monoclausal by tests involving negative polarity, tense,... (make-causative) mono-clausal in terms of case causee must be animate/agentive “productive” (Adapted from Harley 2008:6) 64 In the DM approach, vocabulary items are inserted on a competitive basis, determined by the best fit to the features in a terminal node. In Harley’s approach, following the proposal in Miyagawa 1998 the lexical causative head selects the root as its complement, while in syntactic causatives, the same causative head takes an ‘argument-structurally complete complement’ – roughly, a full vP. This is illustrated in the following structures: (4)a. Lexical causative vP DP Taro-ga v’ v0 -s P V0 kae DP Tenopura-o b. Taro-ga tenoeura-o kae-s(--). Taro-N palm-A return-CAUS ‘Taro changes his attitude suddenly.’ (Harley 2008:31) b. Syntactic causative vP2 DP Taroo v’ v0CAUS -sase vP1 DP Hanako v’ v0 P DP Pizza - tabe ‘eat’ d. Taroo-ga Hanako-ni pizza-o Taro-N Hanako-D pizza-A ‘Taro made Hanako eat pizza.’ tabe-sase-ta eat-CAUS-PST (Harley 2008:30) 65 Note that Taro is the causer argument both in lexical (4a & b) and syntactic (4c &d) causatives but the former involves the causer combining with an idiosyncratic meaning of the predicate while the meaning of the syntactic causative is predictable from the combination of the causer argument with the causee and the event of causing. An important consequence of Harley’s analysis is the difference between the lexical causative head v0 and inchoative v0 head. Harley analyzes these items as interchangeable rather than simultaneously present in the causatives of various verbs. Proposals which are closely linked to Harley’s analysis on the distinction between lexical and syntactic causatives are found in the work of Travis (2000), Pylkkanen (2002) among others. These explorations make use of low and high attachment sites for causative morphemes in various languages to account for cross-linguistic variation of these structures. According to these explorations, lexical vs. syntactic use of causatives result from the attachment site of the causative head either to a higher functional projection (vP), or the lexical VP, and even lower projection (such as ROOT). As Pylkkanen (2002) and Harley (1995, 2008) argue, the attachment of the causative head to a higher projection (vP or VP) results in syntactic causatives, while the attachment of the causative head to a ROOT results in lexical causatives. Travis (2000) uses a Hale & Keyser-style (henceforth, H &K 1993) analysis with VPshells. She argues that in Tagalog and Malagasy, the attachment of the same causative morpheme to different parts of the syntactic tree may result in different meanings and productivity of causative structures. Pylkkanen (2002) and others build on this notion and claim that the distinction between lexical and ‘syntactic’ causatives follows from the 66 ‘size’ of the complement the CAUSE 14 takes: a causative head may select a categoryneutral ROOT, a VP, or the whole phase vP (which has an external argument in it). In Travis’s analysis as in Harley’s, the causative heads that select the vP project an external argument. They will be referred to as phase-selecting causatives following Chomsky (1999 & 2001), McGinnis (2000, 2001a & b), and Arad (2003 & 2004) among others. As noted above, in Harley’s (2008) trees above, the external argument is introduced in the specifier of the CAUSE vP. However, following Kratzer (1996) Pylkkanen (2002) argues that external arguments are instead syntactically introduced by a Voice0, separate from the cause v0, and the variation in the causative heads bundling with Voice0 results in important crosslinguistic differences in terms of productivity and meaning 15. Specifically, she argued that in some languages the CAUSE v0 does not bundle with the Voice0 and does not project an external argument. This happens in adversity causatives where the CAUSE introduces the causing event but crucially does not the external argument. I will adopt this assumption here. Below in section 2.6 I will show that in Georgian causative structures, like in Finnish desiderative and Japanese adversity causatives (Pylkkanen 2002), the causative head may not project the external argument and therefore, other functional heads such as Voice are argued to be responsible for introducing them. 2.3 Inchoative-causative alternation 2.3.0 Introduction 14 CAUSE stands for the causative head in Pylkkanen’s dissertation (2002). I will use this term for further reference to the causative head. 15 See the discussion on the motivation of the Voice head in the Introduction. 67 As noted in the introduction, English has an inchoative/causative alternation (8), often called the melt/melt alternation: (5) a. Ice melted. b. Bill melted ice. The same verb may participate in the alternation without a change in morphological marking. In other languages, such as Georgian, the same alternation may entail a change in the morphological shape of a verb. 2.3.1. Causatives of inchoative verbs The inchoative-causative alternation in Georgian is marked with a- (7) or - (6). Note that the morphological marking of inchoative causatives is distinct from that of unergative-causative or transitive-causative alternations (which usually result in make X do V meanings). The latter will be discussed in Sections 2.3 and 2.4. (6) 16 -prefixed causatives formed from inchoative and reflexive verbs in Georgian: Inchoative Causative a. da- imal- a prev- intr- hid- Aor 16 ‘X hid.’ damal- a prev- - hid- Aor ‘Y hid X.’ b. da- ibana prev- intr- wash- Aor ‘X bathed.’ daban- a prev- - bathe- Aor ‘Y bathed X.’ c. da- iɣal- a prev- intr- tire- Aor daɣal- a prev- - tired- Aor The abbreviations used here are: prev- for the preverbal aspectual and directionality marker; intrIntransitivity marker in general, Aor- for the Aorist screeve morpheme; thmw- for thematic markers in verbs; CAUS- for the causative marker; stands for zero allomorph of the CAUSE, etc. The term screeve in Kartvelian Linguistics stands for the verb conjugation paradigm in terms of Aspect, Tense, and Mood. There are 11 such screeves in Georgian verbal morphology (Aronson 1990). 68 (7) ‘X got tired.’ Lit: ‘Y tired X’. 17 d. ga- t’q’- da prev- break- intrans-Aor ‘X broke.’ 18 gat’ex- a prev- - break- Aor ‘Y broke X.’ e. i- ch’r- eba intr- cut- thmw- Aor ‘X got cut’. gach’rPrev- - cut‘Y cut X.’ a Aor a-prefixed causatives formed from inchoative verbs a. gai- ɣo prev-intr- open- Aor ‘Y opened.’ gaaɣo prev- CAUS- open-Aor ‘X opened the Y’. b. gamo- cxv- a prev- bake- Aor ‘Y baked.’ gamo- acxo prev- CAUS- bake- Aor ‘X baked Y.’ (6b) is a reflexive verb; (6a, c, & d) are inchoatives. The difference between (6) and (7) is in the allomorphy of causative morpheme. Notice that the causative morpheme realized as a-/- is root-adjacent, i.e. it linearly precedes the root. It might be argued that the allomorphy of CAUSE is phonologically root-conditioned since a- occurs in vowel‘defective’ consonantal roots while - occurs in elsewhere contexts, i.e. it may occur both with vowel-defective and consonantal roots as shown in (6e). The VIs inserted for CAUSE with their conditioning environments can be shown in the following in which the subscript notation [-] indicates a class of non-syllabic roots: (8) 17 a. a- CAUSE / [ _____ROOT-] 19 Note that the free English translation of (9c) is not as ‘natural’ as in other examples in (6). This is because the inventory of verbs participating in the inchoative/causative alternation is language-specific. 18 It should be noted that (6a-b) are reflexive forms and they are marked with the same prefix i- as (6c-d), which are inchoative. This prefix is uniformly present in all reflexives in Georgian such as body verbs but it is not systematic in inchoatives though. 69 b. - CAUSE / elsewhere This sensitivity of the VI to the syllabicity of roots may be taken as evidence that the causatives of inchoative verbs are “low attachment” in the sense of Pylkkanen (2002, 2008). This means that the causative head takes the root for its complement. This alternation is fairly productive in Georgian and applies to a subset of monadic verbs resulting in transitive structure. It has been already shown by many (cf. Pylkkanen (2002) & Harley (2008)) that if the causative head takes the root as its complement, then the resulting structure may have idiosyncratic meaning, and that it may acquire the property of ‘listedness’, which is characteristic of lexical causatives in various languages. This type of idiomatic interpretation may sometimes be present in lexical causatives but not necessarily so (See Harley 2006 and Levin & Rappoport 1999 for further details). Following Harley (2008) I assume that CAUSE merges in the same position as other light verb elements (such as vBECOME in inchoatives, realized as i-/- in (6)-(7)). This head takes RootP (represented as P) as its complement 20. I propose that the derivation of causatives from inchoatives involves the root, which is verbalized by the vP introducing causative meaning into the structure (CAUSE). The allomorphy of the CAUSE head in such causatives may be determined by the Root, since no overt material intervenes between them as seen in (9). As we have seen above, the item a- realizes the CAUSE v0 when the Root is syllable-defective. Thus, based on this 19 It could be argued that in Georgian a- also realizes the functional head, which is responsible for the projection of the theme argument. I would call the feature [TRANS] on vP that may be realized with the same phonological exponent and this will be a primary exponence of a- . This proposal will be elaborated below Section 2.4. 20 We will be referring to such events as mono-eventive further in this work because it does not combine two independent events. 70 evidence and following Embick (2009)’s proposal on the phonological conditioning of morphemes as indicating their non-cyclicity, I conclude that the CAUSE head is a noncyclic head. It is expected that in such reduced transitive structure, the head CAUSE may still ‘see’ the Root and show the root-conditioned allomorphy. Given these preliminaries, the structure of causatives resulting from inchoative/causative alternations may be sketched in the following: (9)a. tamar-ma p’ur-i T-Erg bread-Acc ‘Tamar baked bread.’ gamo- acxPrev- CAUS- bake- o. 3S/Aor TP AspP VoiceP DPNOM/ERG causer tamar-ma Asp0 gamo-, etc. Voice’ vPCAUS P DPACC theme p’uri‘bread’ T0 -o, -a, -s (-features) cx ‘bake’ Voice0 - v0 CAUSE a-/- In this tree, a full specification of the functional heads merging in the derivation of lexical causative is given. This derivation involves not only the causative head, which is of primary concern in this work, but also the Voice, which introduces the external argument. Cross-linguistically, Tense and Asp0 heads are introduced in various positions of the left periphery of the clause. In Georgian and related languages where the Asp0 is realized in the first position of the template one might argue that it must be the latest head 71 merging into the structure assuming bottom-up derivation of words and sentences in syntax. However, this may not be true as it is evident that the morphemes realizing Tense and Series features are in the word-final position fused with the person agreement markers of non-local subjects and objects. As seen in (9), Tns merges later than the CAUSE and other vPs. Thus, it may be assumed that the linearization of the VIs inserted into the Tns and Asp0 heads may be subject to some post-syntactic rules and languagespecific well-formedness requirements. The exact nature of these rules is not of concern here, but note that in the future discussions on the derivation of causative and applicative structures, we will be assuming the existence of such rules and that they are applied either before or after the Vocabulary Insertion (For example a metathesis rule applies after vocabulary insertion, argued in Embick and Noyer (2001)). In positioning TP above the AspP we follow Travis’s (2000) and others’ arguments based on the study of event structure in various languages in which the category of Asp0 is closely associated with the vP delimitation and presumably, it is merged above the latter projection regardless of its relation with Voice. As for the argument structure, causatives of inchoative verbs involve a causer argument, which I assume is not projected by the CAUSE but by the Voice0 head (following Kratzer (1994) and Pylkkanen (2002, 2008)). The theme argument is assumed to be projected as the complement of the Root as argued by many in the literature. The evidence that these structures exhibit a simple clausal structure may be seen from the case-marking in (9). The causer is marked with ergative case just like the external argument of a normal transitive verb while the theme is marked with 72 accusative/absolutive 21 case. The theme argument is projected by the lexical verbal head and its content is sensitive to the selectional properties of this head. I assume that if the structure contains just one clause, only one case-split argument (the causer) is possible in such a clause: (10) tamar-ma gamoacx-o p’ur-i. Tamar-Erg baked-AOR bread-Acc/Abs ‘Tamar baked bread.’ Case assignment follows the ‘mono-clausal’/’mono-eventive’ pattern of transitive structures. 22 Given the data of causatives in Georgian, it can also be suggested that the external argument is introduced by the Voice0 rather than the CAUSE because the causer never composes with the predicate to form idiomatic expressions. Also, if CAUSE projects an external argument with nominative /ergative case, then, in adversity causative structures, where no external argument is projected but the causative head is present, there would be no way to explain why this head does not project the external argument. We return to these questions below in section 2.6. 2.4 Unergative verbs of various types and their causatives 2.4.0 Hale & Keyser (1993, 2002) on unergatives and Noun-Incorporated vPs There are several types of unergative structures in Georgian and their alternation with causatives is unrestricted. The latter involves the addition of a causer argument and the result is that the former external argument of an unergative verb becomes the causee argument of a causative alternate. I assume that, as in other languages, unergative verbs, 21 Since Georgian and related languages display aspectually-conditioned split ergativity (Introduction), it is assumed that the accusative object argument is marked with the absolutive case in the ergative pattern, i.e. in the Aorist series. 22 A note on the choice of terms is due here. I use ‘clause’ to designate a phase-size (Chomsky 1999) unit of syntactic structure, which can be either vP or CP. In this sense, the causatives of transitive verbs with make X do V meaning may contain two ‘clauses’, i.e. two vPs as will be shown later in this chapter. 73 which largely belong to a denominal class such as laugh, cough, cry, etc., are derived through incorporation of bare N0 in a ‘defective’ V0 head (Hale & Keyser 1993, 2002: 15-16). The operation is a type of External Merger (EM) of the sister nodes under adjacency, which is termed conflation in H & K’s (2002:18). 23 The lexical head V0, which may be empty or have a zero spellout, may conflate with the N or Adj projected as its sister. The derivation of argument structure in these constructions proceeds according to the principles of bare phrase structure (Chomsky 1995). H & K take Conflation as a structural ‘pressure’ for the ‘empty’ V0 head to get conflated with its sister node, when the latter is bare N or Adj. This theory of how argument structure of unergatives is built resembles other types of incorporation analyses where the noun incorporates into the v0 head. 24 The derivation of an unergative verb begins with a category-neutral root (Marantz 1997) which contributes the phonological material (in H & K’s terms, the features encoded in the phonological material of the morphemes is a p-signature) to the verb (H & K 2002: 77). This root is also maximally a lexical projection and not an extended projection in which the p-signature is passed onto the verb from a P0 head as in the following: 23 This dissertation crucially distinguishes Noun Incorporation (NI) into V0 head from the Adjective Incorporation (AI). The basis for this comes from the fact that in Georgian NI-ed stems project external arguments which are marked with three different cases while AI verbs project internal arguments, which check just the nominative case across all three series of verbs like unaccusatives. This suggests that AI (Adjective Incorporated) stems have derived subjects, which are VP-internal arguments rather than basegenerated as external arguments. This is why the causatives of NI and AI stems are treated separately in this dissertation. 24 Besides the external argument, which is arguably projected by the Voice0, a Goal/Benefactor argument may be added to the argument structure of such verbs that results in more complex argument structure. 74 (11) a. bottle the wine V V bottle {P} DP the wine {P} {P} {N} bottle (H & K 2002:76) The structure in (11) is derived through the conflation of {P} and {N} first and then P ‘forces’ the merger of the specifier by selection, which is instantiated by the DP the wine. After this merger {P} is conflated with the V0 with further Merge. In Georgian, unergative verbs present a semantically wider variety than in English but they rarely involve structures with location/locatum arguments like those in English (bottle, saddle). As mentioned above, subjects are agentive and they check nom/erg/dative cases against Voice across the present, aorist, and the perfective series much like those of transitive verbs. Here are some examples: (12) Unergative verbs in Georgian k’ivis 25 scream- TH- 3S/Ser ‘He/she screams.’ a. b. shpot- avs agitate- TH- 3S/Ser ‘He/she is agitated.’ 25 The main reason that I consider these verbs ‘unergative’ is that they have external arguments which are assigned nom/erg/dative cases across the three series. However, one may argue that they are very much like inchoative verbs shown in (6)-(7) participating in causative alternation. I consider these two classes separately because first the subjects in (12) are case-alternating like external arguments and second, all these verbs are clearly formed by NI, which is not present in inchoatives in (6)-(7). Also the causative morpheme used in different in these forms. 75 c. q’vir- ishout- TH‘He/she shouts.’ s 3S/Ser d. cimcim- ebs glitterTH- 3S/Ser ‘It is glittering.’ mɣer- is 26 sing- TH- 3S/Ser ‘He/she sings’. e. Note that these verbs do not show any overt morphology marking intransitivity (elsewhere expressed by the prefix i-) as in inchoative alternates shown above (see Appendix A for details). Locatum/location arguments do not merge in these structures either and this excludes the merger of defective {P} in their derivation. It may be argued that the unergative verbs in (12) are derived through root incorporation into an empty v0. Thus the structure is: (13) a. k’iv-i-s ‘X screams’ b. VoiceP Voice’ DPNOM/ERG X Voice0 - vP v0 -- P k’iv ‘scream’ 26 Note also that the verbs in (23) are marked with different theme suffixes (such as –eb, -i, -av), which is primarily defined by the verb class. There is no principled reason why certain verbs show up with either of these markers, since thematic suffixes are the formants inserted for morphological well-formedness. 76 As said above, the unergative/causative alternation may involve the causer and the causee arguments with both the make X do V reading and the iterated causative Z makes X cause Y to do V meaning. Here are examples of make X do V type alternation: (14) Make X do V causatives of unergative verbs a. ak’ivl- ebs CAUS- scream- TH 27- 3S/Ser ‘X makes Y scream.’ b. acimcim- eb- s CAUS- glitterTH- 3S/Ser ‘X makes Y glitter.’ c. amɣerCAUS- sing‘X makes Y sing.’ eb- s TH- 3S/Ser d. acinebCAUS- laughTH‘X makes Y laugh’. s 3S/Ser Notice that the morphological shape of these causatives is similar to the causative alternates of inchoative verbs discussed above. The key differences are that only the prefix a- is inserted in the CAUSE v0, never the - one, thematic marker –eb is added, adjacent to the root. The productivity of this alternation suggests that CAUSE takes an argument-full vP complement and that the head projects the causee argument in the specifier. 27 Recall that ‘thmw’ stands for the thematic marker in these verbs. 77 (15) The causative of unergative ‘a-kivl-eb-s’ X makes Y scream. VoiceP Voice’ DPNOM/ERG causer vPCAUS vP P DPACC v0 Voice0 - v0 CAUSE a- k’ivl ‘scream’ causee The causative is derived through root head-movement to higher functional heads such as CAUSE, and Voice0. Two arguments are projected in this causative structure: the casesplit causer and the accusative causee. This case marking shows the mono-clausal pattern and the causer is assigned the cases of an external argument across three series (nom/erg/dative), while the causee is assigned a structural accusative. I assume that the case-split argument checks its case against Voice0 head via spechead relation when it is marked with ergative and against Tns via Agree when it is marked with nominative. The causee bearing the accusative case may be argued to be checked against the little v0 head whose case probe can search down the structure without incurring the minimality violations. There is no root-conditioned allomorphy associated with the VI a- inserted in CAUSE in these structures. The question is what are the insertion contexts of a- allomorph in these unergatives? Recall that the insertion context for the insertion of a- was determined by the syllabicity of roots in inchoatives (shown in (8)). Apparently, the syllabicity of 78 roots is not relevant in determining the allomorph of cause inserted in the causatives of unergatives. I tentatively posit that the insertion of a- in unergative structures is sensitive to the feature [+ trans] on the v0 head. Thus, this is a ‘different’ a- than the one inserted in the CAUSE merging in the causative alternates of inchoative verbs: (16) VIs for CAUSE in (14) a. a- CAUSE / ___ v0[TRANS] b. a- CAUSE / ___ [Root-] c. - CAUSE/ elsewhere Thus, it may be argued that the VI inserted in CAUSE in these causatives is not sensitive to root properties and the contextual allomorphy attested in the causatives of inchoatives is not at issue here. Given this evidence, I designate the CAUSE as a cyclic in these structures. Stemming from this, it can be argued that the cyclicity of a functional head is relative concept depending on the size of the complement this functional head takes. Again following Embick’s generalizations 1-2, I assume that only the CAUSE head taking the Root complement is A non-cyclic head while the one taking the vP is cyclic. 2.4.1 Adjective-Incorporated (AI) vPs and their causatives In addition to NI (Noun Incorporation) and conflation, H&K (2002) discuss Adjective Incorporation (henceforth, AI) structures that involve a root combining with ‘a nuclear element’ functioning as a predicator. Such ‘predicators’ are like inflectional categories which in some contexts may be ‘defective’ or phonologically unexpressed (H & K 2002: 54-55). In Georgian, adjective-incorporated structures are presumably formed with a 79 similar kind of functional element as shown in (17). The crucial property of these intransitive predicates is that the v0 head does not project an external argument as in NI structures and their highest argument projected in the specifier of VP is case-marked with the nominative case across all series. This property makes AI structures look like unaccusative verbs suggesting that their arguments will behave like derived subjects: (17) AI structures a. c’q’ali ga- mc’vanwater prev- green‘Water became green.’ d - 28 pass- b. xalxi damshviddpeople prev- calm.down- pass‘People calmed down.’ a Aor a Aor In these forms, the roots mc’van ‘green’ and mshvid ‘calm’ first combine with a (a category-defining head) and then the resulting root is conflated with the ‘defective’ V0 head of the lexical projection. The latter head-moves to v0 which is realized with the VI – d in all AI forms. I presume that this vP is the one introducing dynamic intransitive events (such as vGO discussed in Cuervo (2003)). The following structure shows the derivation of such Adjective-Incorporated verbs: (18) The structure for AI verbs a. c’q’ali ga- mc’van- da water prev- green- pass- 3S/Aor ‘Water became green’. 28 The suffix –d is analyzed as the passive voice marker in the traditional grammar but this work analyzes it as the VI inserted into v0 head of the unergative verbs generally. 80 b. vPGO v0 VP V’ DPNOM c’q’ali ‘water’ V0 - AdjP mc’van ‘green’ v0 -d a AI structures in Georgian can alternate with causatives by adding a CAUSE head to the functional layer of the clause imbuing a cause X to become Adj reading to the resultant structure: (19) AI intransitives Causative a. mo- tvinier- da prev- tamed- pass- Aor ‘X was tamed.’ b. mo- atvinier- a prev- CAUS- tamed- Aor Lit: ‘X made Y become tame.’ c. ač’rel- d- a prev- color- pass- Aor ‘It became multi-colored’. d. aač’rel- a prev- CAUS- color- Aor Lit: ‘X made Y multi-colored.’ e. ga- lamazda prev- beautiful- pass- Aor ‘It became beautiful.’ f. ga- alamaza prev- CAUS- beautiful- Aor Lit: ‘X made Y beautiful.’ g. mo- č’k’vian- da prev- smartpass- Aor ‘He/she came to his/her senses’. h. mo- ač’k’vian- a prev- CAUS- smart- Aor Lit: ‘X made Y sensible.’ i. ga- nat- da prev- light- pass- Aor ‘It became day-like’/ ‘It dawned’. j. ga- anat- a prev- CAUS- light- Aor Lit: ‘X made Y lightened.’ 81 Again this alternation closely resembles the inchoative/causative alternation with its morphological realization. Recall that the VI a- is inserted in two-place causative alternates combining the causer and the theme arguments. AI verbs resemble inchoatives in their argument structure, and their causatives are also similar to those of inchoatives. The causer argument is added to the argument structure of unaccusative verbs and the alternation is productive: causatives may be derived from any AI predicate. Based on the argument structure of these causatives, it may be argued that as in lexical causatives of inchoative verbs, CAUSE selects for the RootP (P) complement in these structures. Therefore, it is expected that no causee argument is introduced by CAUSE or any other functional head resulting in regular transitive frame as of inchoatives. This could be due to the fact that the alternation is a part of a more general inchoative-causative one. Recall that in these structures, the external argument does not cause another agentive argument to perform a certain action, rather the causer performs the caused action itself. Therefore, the head of the P does not project the causee argument. These selectional properties of various verbal heads may be found in AI predicates: (20) The causative of AI unergative verbs a. bich’-eb- ma xalx- i boy- pl- Erg people- Acc ‘Boys calmed people down.’ daamšvid- es. prev- CAUS- calm- Aor/3S.pl 82 b. VoiceP DPNOM/ERG bich’eb-ma ‘boys’ Voice0 - vP VP DPACC Voice’ CAUSE -aV’ theme mshvid xalx-i ‘calm’ ‘people’ V0 As expected, there is no root-conditioned allomorphy associated with the CAUSE. The exponent a- realizes CAUSE in all environments shown in (19). By hypothesis the CAUSE can be realized with the a- in the contexts where the v0 head is specified for [+ trans] feature. We assume that this feature is present on v0 merged in AI structures as well. 2.4.2 Syntactic and iterated causatives of unergative verbs When the causatives in (14) further causativize and undergo X makes Y cause Z to do V alternation, beyond the causer argument who is the initiator of the core event, two causee arguments are projected and both are inherently agentive. Given this argument structure, the insertion of the second VI for CAUSE –in shown in (21) is expected because the structure becomes ditransitive projecting one causer and two causee arguments. I assume that two CAUSE heads are merged in these structures introducing two separate causing events. The case-marking of arguments is again ‘mono-eventive’ only the highest causer argument bears the nom/erg/dative cases of an external argument. Of the two causees, the 83 higher one receives the structural dative case while the lower causee checks the accusative case. Note also that the case of the higher causee argument does not change in the Present and Aorist series since it is marked with the dative while the case of the lower causee changes from the Present to the Aorist series which indicates that it is marked with the accusative: (21) Syntactic causative with X makes Y cause Z to do V meaning in the Aorist series a. dato-m nino-s natia daak’ivl- eb- ina D-Erg N-Dat N-Acc Prev- CAUS- scream- TH- CAUS- 3S/Ser ‘Dato made Nino cause Natia to scream.’ b. dato-m aleksi-s santeli aacimcim- eb- ina D-Erg A-Dat candle-Acc Prev- CAUS- glitter- TH- CAUS- 3S/Ser ‘Dato made Alex cause candle to glitter.’ c. dato-m nana-s aleksi aaq’vir- eb- ina D-Erg N-Dat A-Acc Prev-CAUS- shout- TH- CAUS- 3S/Ser ‘Dato made Nana cause Alex to shout.’ Thus, the syntactic structure of iterated causatives contains two causative heads which introduce two separate causing events to the structure and I claim that the dative causee is projected in the specifier of the CAUSE which is vP and its case is checked against the head of this projection. I assume that the case-split argument checks its nominative case against Tns and ergative case against Voice via government. The accusative case on the lower causee argument may be checked against the same v0 which checks the dative case on the higher causee assuming that the probe of the accusative case feature may be checked first due to bottom-up derivation and when the dative causee is merged its dative cause may be checked via spec-head relation. Observe these structural relations in the following tree: 84 (22) The syntactic structure of iterated syntactic causatives a. a-k’ivl-eb-in-eb-s ‘X makes Y cause Z to scream’ b. VoiceP DPNOM/ERG Voice’ causer X vPCAUS Voice0 vP CAUSE1 invP CAUSE2 -a v’ DPDAT causee Y VP v0 DPACC k’ivl ‘scream’ causee Z This analysis of the argument structure of causatives maintains Pylkkanen’s notion that the CAUSE does not project the phrasal argument cross-linguistically but the event one. As seen in (22), further causativization of make X do V causatives is possible for the causatives formed from unergative verbs, but there is no iteration of the individual VIs realizing the CAUSE. 29 Instead, the exponent –in presumably realizes the outer CAUSE in these structures. At this point it may be suggested that the CAUSEs can be realized with two different VIs in these structures. I tentatively suggest that the insertion context for the –in allomorph of CAUSE is the feature [+ditrans] of the v0 head. Another point of relevant interest is that when –in is realized in a given form, a- is also inserted into the second CAUSE head. This type of mutual dependency between two morphemes may not 29 It will be shown below that the iteration of causative morphemes is possible only in the perfective series verbs in Georgian and that the iterated suffix -in marks totally different functional category. 85 be an isolate fact of Georgian. It may be explained with the discontinuous feeding mechanism when one morpheme ‘conditions’ the insertion of another into a different functional head. Thus, the [+ ditrans] feature on v0 can be a contextual feature responsible for the insertion of –in in the CAUSE and presumably, the insertion of a- can also be sensitive to the same feature. Here is the list of VIs for CAUSE: (23) Vocabulary items for CAUSE: a. a- CAUSE / ___ [Root-] b. a- CAUSE / ___ v0[TRANS], [DITRANS] c. –in CAUSE / ___ v0[DITRANS] d. - CAUSE/ elsewhere Notice also that the thematic marker (-eb) can iterate in the causative shown in (22). According to the morphological literature (Embick 1997, 2003, among others), thematic markers are not usually associated with functional heads. Presumably, they are inserted just due to well-formedness requirements, as dissociated morphemes. The iteration of one such formant –eb in (22) may be accounted for with the series feature of the clause since it occurs in the Present series while the verbs in (21), used in the Aorist series, lack these iterated markers. Their distribution looks also to be associated with the causative marker –in often preceding and following the latter. However, there is no fixed pattern of correlation between this causative marker and the thematic syllable –eb. Below, this correlation will be explored in greater detail. It is notable that further causativization of the lexical causatives involving AI structures is also possible resulting in the same X makes Y do V meaning. The 86 morphological realization of the resulting causative is very similar to those derived from unergative verbs: (24) Causatives of AI-incorporated verbs a. mo- atvinier- eb- ina prev- CAUS- tame- TH- CAUS- Aor ‘X made Y tame Z.’ b. ga- alamazeb- ina prev- CAUS- beautiful- TH- CAUS-Aor ‘X made Y embellish Z.’ c. daamaxinj- eb- ina prev- CAUS- uglyTH- CAUS- Aor ‘X made Y make Z ugly’. d. ga- amc’van- eb- ina prev- CAUS- greenTH- CAUS- Aor ‘X made Y make Z green.’ Recall from the discussion above that the VIs a- and -in are inserted into two CAUSEs in unergative structures that add the second causee argument resulting in iterated causative meaning make X cause Y to do V. Here only X make Y cause X V reading is possible and still two CAUSEs merge introducing two causing events and two lower arguments represent the causee and the theme. The insertion of the two VIs for CAUSE is predicted given the ditranitive structure of these constructions. As noted in (23), –in is inserted in the environment of v0 with the [+ ditrans] feature. I assume that the causatives of AI predicates with X made Y to do V meaning have the following derivation: (25) AI causatives a. ga- alamazeb- ina prev-CAUS- beautiful- TH- CAUS- 3S/Aor ‘X caused Y to make Z beautiful.’ 87 b. VoiceP DPNOM/ERG causer X vP Voice’ vP vCAUSE -in vP DPDAT causee Y VP DPACC theme Z Voice0 - vCAUS a- v’ v0 V0 V0 lamaz Adjective-Incorporated causative with a make X do V reading should show the complex internal structure on the syntactic tests. These tests can be the same as shown with the similar causative structures of unaccusative verbs: (26) VP-modifying adverbial test a. dato st’udent’eb-s a-tviniereb-in-ebs D-Nom students-Dat CAUS-tame-CAUS‘Dato makes students tame monkeys again.’ b. isev Again dato D a-tviniereb-in-ebs CAUS-tame-CAUS- st’udentebs students maimunebs monkeys isev. again maimunebs. monkeys (27) Depictive modification test a. dato D-Nom st’udenteb-s students-Dat aɣeb- ineb- s CAUS- paint- CAUS- TH- 3S saxls house gaxarebulebs merry-Dat Lit: ‘Dato makes students merry open the house.’ b. dato st’udenteb-s D-Nom students-Dat gaxarebul-i merry-Nom aɣeb- ineb- s CAUS- paint- CAUS- TH- 3S saxls house 88 c. ?? dato st’udenteb-s D-Nom students-Dat aɣeb- ineb- s CAUS- paint- CAUS- TH- 3S saxls house gaxarebul-i. merry-Nom. ‘Dato makes students open the house merry.’ The VP-modifying adverbial isev ‘again’ can scope over the matrix (the causing event) or the embedded (the caused event) depending on the attachment site. In (26a), isev ‘again’ modifies the caused event entailing meaning that students tame monkeys repeatedly due to Dato’s initiation. In (26b), the meaning is different since the same modifier scopes over the causee’s action, i.e. Dato repeatedly causes students to tame monkeys. The causer Dato and the causee students may not be projected into the separate clauses (CPs), but the adverbial scope facts suggest that the adverbial modifies two vPs, which can be argued to be phases in the sense of Chomsky (1999) discussed in the introduction of the dissertation. As for the depictive modification test in (27), when the depictive modifies the causer Dato it is more natural to use it more locally, i.e. before the VP merges as in (27b) rather than at the end of the structure where the depictive of the lower causee is still fine (27a). This indicates that depictive modifiers are sensitive to locality and we assume that the depictives of the causer and the causee may be projected in different ‘clauses’ taking the latter as a smaller structural unit than the clause with the full CP. Thus, we may assume that bi-eventive analysis of these complex predicates is possible. 2.5 Transitive/causative alternation 2.5.0 Introduction 89 This section recapitulates some of the observations discussed in the previous parts, applying them to transitive predicates. These are all syntactic causatives of make X do V type, and the morphology is similar to those formed from other classes of verbs. The rest of the section is organized as follows: in 2.5.1 the basic type of causative structures derived from transitive verbs are discussed as well as their complex syntax; section 2.5.2 present extensions of the analysis for iterated causatives. 2.5.1 X makes Y do V alternation Transitive predicates allow a CAUSE and a VoiceP whose head projects an external causer argument. The morphological shape of such causatives shows the insertion of the two VIs a- and –in into the CAUSE head. The prefix a- is linearized before the root, as in other kinds of causatives above. Here are some examples: (28) Transitive Causative a. k’rep- s pick- 3S/Ser ‘X picks it.’ b. ak’rep- ineb- s CAUS- pick- CAUS- TH- 3S/Ser ‘X makes Y pick it.’ c. cvli- s exchange- TH- 3S/Ser ‘X exchanges it.’ d. acvlevin- eb- s CAUS- change- CAUS- TH- 3S/Ser ‘X makes Y exchange it.’ (29) a. apas- eb- s 30 CAUS- praise- TH- 3S/Ser ‘X praises it.’ b. apas- eb- ineb- s CAUS-praise- TH- CAUS- TH- 3S/Ser ‘X makes Y praise it.’ c. ashen- ebCAUS- build- TH- d. ashenCAUS- build- s 3S/Ser eb- ineb- s TH- CAUS- TH- 3S/Ser Note that some of the transitive forms in (38) are marked with a- and some with - for transitivity. I assume that a- is the VI inserted in the v0 of certain verbs, specifically, in those, which have –eb as a thematic marker (38a & e), while - is an elsewhere item (38c & g). We are not concerned with the realization of this v0, because the issue here is realization of the causative head in syntactic causatives of the make X do V type. 30 90 ‘X builds it.’ ‘X makes Y build it.’ Notice that there are two different patterns of causative marking in (28) and (29). The verbs pick and exchange have the zero phonological item for the CAUSE in their transitive frame and then doubled causative marking of the syntactic causative of X makes Z do V alternates, i.e. in (28a & b), both a- and –in are inserted for the CAUSE. I may argue that in the causative alternate of these verbs only one CAUSE is realized with two phonological exponents a-/-in since in their transitive frame in (28a & c), no causative marker shows up. To explain this pattern of the realization of CAUSE, recall from Section 2.3 that the null phonological item for CAUSE has elsewhere distribution and it shows up both in syllable-defective and syllable-full environments. Thus, it may be assumed that this null exponent of CAUSE is present in (28a & c). However, the causatives of both sets of verbs are marked with the exponents a- and -in and I argue that the stacking of the two morphemes indicates two CAUSEs both in (28) and (29). The insertion of two VIs for CAUSE can again be explained with the conditioning environments of a- and –in specified in (23). Both VIs can occur in the contexts of v0 bearing [+ ditrans] feature and here the structure satisfies this condition. However, the suffix –in may or may not follow the thematic marker –eb, which is iterated in (28d) & (29). The causative in (28d) is unusual in that it is marked with –evin rather than with -in. I claim that the simple (-in) and the complex causative marker (-evin) are allomorphs of CAUSE. This comes from the observation that diachronically the affix –ev is derived from the thematic marker –eb. One might think that these simple and complex 91 allomorphs of CAUSE may be sensitive to the syllabic structure of roots they attach to (as sketched in (30)): (30) a. –in CAUSE [ ROOT[+ ] ____ ] b. – evin CAUSE [ ROOT [-] ___ ] On the surface, it appears as if –in is inserted into CAUSE with the vowel-full roots, while –evin, which contains the assimilated thematic marker, is inserted in syllabledefective roots. However, the data in (29) does not show that the post-base thematic marker –eb is sensitive to the syllabicity of roots. The exact distribution of thematic affixes is not a concern in this work and it may be explored in a separate paper in the future. The relevant question, then, is why the thematic marker is ‘absent’ in (28b) and the causative suffix –in appears immediately adjacent to the root. Notice that the root contains the rhyme –ep, which one might think diachronically could also have been the thematic marker –eb subjected to word-final devoicing of bilabial stops. However, this hypothesis may not be true given the vowel alternating roots of this verb in the present and the aorist series which are ‘k’rep-k’rip ‘pick’ displaying the umlaut pattern of root alternation. Based on this observation I suggest that v-k’rep cannot be analyzed as v-k’rep ‘I am picking’ in which the phonologically modified thematic marker –eb/-ep is analyzed separately in the causative. I also argue that the absence of the iterated –eb in (28) may NOT be taken as the lack of the second CAUSE in the causative alternates since as we have argued in Section 2.3 the thematic marker –eb is associated with the series features appearing in the present series present and future screeve forms in a number of ergative and transitive verbs as shown in the following: 92 (31) Unergatives and transitives with –eb in the present and the future screeves a. v- imɣer- eb 1S- voice- sing- TH ‘I will sing’. b. v- icek’v- eb 1S- voice- dance- TH ‘I will dance.’ c. v- ak’et- eb 1S- CAUS- do- TH ‘I am doing it.’ d. v- ek’amat- eb- i 1S- voice- argue- TH- Tns ‘I am arguing’. Based on these examples, it can be argued that the distribution of the thematic marker –eb across various verb classes is not always linked to the presence of the CAUSE and it shows up in elsewhere contexts both adjacent and distanced from the Root/base. The lack of the thematic marker –eb in (28b) may be explained due to the structure of root itself. It may be that a readjustment rule applies in the post-syntactic component and deletes this affix in the environment of identical or near-identical phonological element like the –ep in ‘k’rep’ ‘pick’. All other forms in (28)-(29) may be argued to contain –eb or its modified phonological element –evin the latter being sensitive to the syllabic structure of roots. Now the derivation of these complex causative structures is shown in the following tree: (32) The causative of a transitive verb a. ashen- eb- ineb- s CAUS- build- TH- CAUS- TH- 3S ‘X makes Y build Z’. 93 b. VoiceP DPNOM/ERG Causer vP Voice’ Voice0 CAUSE2 -in CAUSE1 a- vP vPDO v’ DPDAT VP DPACC Theme v0 V0 shen‘build’ In this structure, CAUSE selects for the vPDO complement. The external causer argument is projected by the Voice and the vDO introduces the dative causee in the causative alternate that receives agentive interpretation. The case checking pattern is similar here as in other double-CAUSE structures above and we do not repeat it here. It is expected that these causatives containing phase-complete vPs will behave like syntactically complex structures on the adverbial scope and the depictive modification tests: (33) VP-modifying adverbials a. giam G-Erg eliso-s E-Dat k’oncert’i concert sc’rapad quickly ča- ac’erina prev-CAUS- record- CAUS- 3S ‘Gia made Eliso quickly record the whole concert.’ b. giam G elisos E k’oncert’i concert cha-a-c’er-in-a prev-CAUS-record-CAUS-3S sc’rapad. quickly 94 In (33a), the adverbial modifier is agent-oriented, which may be interpreted as the adverbial scoping over the causing event i.e. Gia quickly made Eliso record the concert, while in (33b), the adverbial modifies the recording event, i.e. Gia caused Eliso to record the concert quickly. Thus, the causative structures are derived in the syntax and word derivation parallels the syntactic derivation. The depictive modification test also allows us to diagnose the bi-eventive properties of these causatives as shown in the following examples: (34) Depictive modification of the causer and the causee a. gia-m eliso-s k’oncert’i cha- ac’er- ina daɣlil- s. G-Erg E-Dat concert prev-CAUS- record- CAUS- 3S tired- Dat ‘Gia made Eliso record the concert tired.’ b. ?? gia-m eliso-s G-Erg E-Dat c. ?? gia-m G-Erg eliso-s E-Dat daɣlil-ma tired-Erg k’oncert’i concert k’oncert’i concert cha- ac’er- ina. 31 prev-CAUS-record- CAUS- 3S cha- ac’er- ina prev- CAUS- record- CAUS- 3S daɣlil-ma. tired-Erg As seen in (34), the depictive phrase ‘tired’ is associated with the causee Eliso rather than with the causer Gia in (34a) because the depictive is marked with the dative case as a result of the copying rule applied at the Morphological Structure to the case features of the head noun (Halle 1991). This results in the agreement of the case features between the depictive and the noun. The identical case marking of Eliso and the depictive in (34a) and relative acceptability of such modification may be argued to be linked to the modification 31 It should be noted though that the ergative depictive is relatively fine immediately following Gia such as in the following: gia-m daɣlil-ma Elisos k’oncert’i cha-a- c’er- in-a ‘Gia tired made Eliso record the concert’. 95 of the recording event by this depictive, while the relative unacceptability of the structure in (34b &c ) may be due to the locality constraints on the position of the depictive and modified element. Thus, it may be argued that the causer is not in the same domain as the depictive phrase in (34c) making its depictive modification ungrammatical. Having illustrated the complex syntactic structure of productive causatives in Georgian, now I will turn to the iteration of various types of causatives before discussing other types of causative alternations such as those of adversity and psych verbs. 2.5.2 Iterated causatives Travis (2000) shows in both in Malagasy and Tagalog the causative morpheme can iterate, provided there is an intervening morpheme. In these languages, the meaning of such morphological idiosyncrasy is understood as ‘cause X make Y do V.’ This syntactic causative arguably stands for two causative heads merged in the syntax. Travis suggests that in such structures, the causative morpheme closest to the root is the lexical causative while the others are productive causatives. This is because in both languages, the lexical causative morpheme and the productive causative morpheme are the same (an- and pagrespectively) and in Tagalog, when the productive causative morpheme is added to the lexical causative form the lexical causative morpheme disappears. Travis provides further evidence that the iteration of causatives in Malagasy is attested when a lexical causative turns into a productive syntactic causative. Each causative morpheme adds an additional agent, so that one-place verb becomes two-place predicate, and a two place predicate three place predicate, etc. Serratos (2008) also discusses the existence of such causatives in Chemeheuvi and argues that the iteration of the causative morpheme is 96 possible only when a Low Attachment causative is further causativized resulting in the structure X causes Y to make Z do V meaning: (35) Chemeheuvi causatives a. Nüü-k manga-y 1sg-cop 3sg-anim.vis-obl ‘I am making the girl sing.’ na’üntci-tci girl-NPN.obl huvi-tu-tu’i-yü-‘ümü. song-caus-caus-pres b. Ann Johni na-ha’ü-sunn-tu’i-ngu-tu’i-vü. Ann-Nom John-obl refl-good-think-caus-mom-caus-past ‘Ann made John like her/himself.’ (Serratos, 2008:6) Notice that stacking of causatives in (35a) is possible without an intervening morpheme while in (35b), the morpheme –ngu interferes between these two suffixes. This means that some languages iterate the same morpheme to mark X causes Y do V syntactic causative while other languages (like Georgian) mark such structures with different morphemes such as a-/-in, i.e. two VIs inserted into the CAUSE. This morphological idiosyncrasy can be interpreted given the Late Insertion model of the DM at the PF component of the grammar and the phonological rules operative at this level. Topuria’s (1967) grammar of the Svan language shows the examples of causative morpheme iteration: (36)a. xat’x- unāl- une return- CAUS- … - CAUS- tense ‘X makes Y return something to somebody.’ b. xa-k’r- unasg- une open- CAUS-… - CAUS- tense ‘X makes Y close the door.’ Lashx dialect of Svan (Topuria 1967) These examples of the iterated causative –un suffix show similar distribution to those shown in Travis (2000) and Serratos (2008). The first causative marker shows up in the post-base position and the second after the intervening morphemes (-al and –asg 97 respectively). The first iteration is attested with the causative alternate of the transitive verb to return whose root may also be used in an intransitive frame with the meaning ‘he returned’. Related data in Georgian shows that both frames of the intransitive: ‘He returned’ and ‘He returned X to Y’ are available with the same root. The difference is in the Voice morphology: the transitive frame is marked with the low applicative prefix (i-) while the intransitive one is marked with the suffix –d (often referred to as the passive marker in the traditional grammar): (37) ‘Return’ in Georgian a. da- g- ibrun- a prev- 2O- applic- return- Aor ‘X retuned Y to you’ b. dabrun- da prev- return- pass - Aor ‘X returned.’ It is evident that the Svan causative in (34a) corresponds to Georgian (35a) and the two iterated morphemes mark the CAUSE (and presumably the transitive v0). The Mingelian data provided in Kajaia (2001) suggests that the iteration of causative morphemes is possible in the present perfect (evidential) screeve of the perfective series: (38) Mingrelian causatives a. u-č’ar-ap-u-ap-u(n) ‘make X write.’ (perf.) b. u-tol-ap-u-ap-u(n) ‘make X peel’ (perf.) c. u-z-ap-u-ap-u(n) ‘make X mix dough’ (perf.) Similar morphological structure is available in Georgian in the perfective screeves (in the pluperfect and the conjunctive perfect) where evidentiality may also figure in the interpretation of the Pluperfect forms. Observe the following forms: (39) Conjunctive Perfect forms of causatives in Georgian 98 a. ga- m- ek’eteb- ineb- in32 prev-1S- recip - make- TH- CAUS- TH- CAUS‘I (apparently) would have made X do V’. os scrv- 3O 33 b. gam- erecx- ineb- inos prev- 1S- recip- wash- CAUS- TH- CAUS- scrv- 3O ‘I (apparently) would have made X wash Y’ c. dam- erek’- ineb- inos prev- 1S- recip- call- CAUS- TH- CAUS- scrv- 3O ‘I (apparently) would have made X to call Y’. Notice that the difference between these Georgian and Mingrelian iterated causatives and those found in Svan (in (36)) is that the iteration of the causative morpheme marks the make X do V causative and that these are the structures where at least separate causer and causee arguments are projected. It is also clear that, in Georgian and Mingrelian, the iterated causative morpheme does not add any argument or another CAUSE to the argument structure of these transitive verbs. It should stand for some other functional category. I will attempt to identify this functional head shortly after listing some morphological and syntactic idiosyncrasies of the Perfective series verbs in these languages. Based on the preliminary evidence, the iteration of causative morphemes in Georgian and Mingrelian marks just the causative alternates of transitive verbs which are interpreted with make X do V meaning. Some of these unusual characteristics of iterated causatives in the perfective relevant to the analysis of double causative marking are: 32 Here the gloss ‘recip’ is provided for the reciprocal marker e-, which is multifunctional phonological exponent realizing Voice0 and/or a little v0 in various verbs. The syncretism between these various instances of e- will be analyzed in Section 2.8 dealing with the psychological verbs and their causatives in Georgian. 33 I gloss the second causative suffix as CAUS both in Georgian and Mingrelian for the time being until we come up with an explanation for what this morpheme stands for in these languages. 99 (40) a. The prefix u- marks high applicative meaning in the perfective screeves both in Mingrelian and Georgian because there is no recipient, source, or possessor relation (characteristic of low applicatives) detected between the applied argument and the theme in these structures. b. The causer argument is assigned the dative case in these series and it triggers the m-set agreement normally associated with objects of the transitive verbs attested in the present and the aorist series 34; c. The perfective series is the only tense/mood/aspect paradigm where evidentiality plays a certain role in interpretation (Georgian- Aronson 1990, Mingrelian- Kajaia 2001, and in Svan --Topuria 1967, Sumbat’ova 1999). Evidentiality denotes the morphological marking of the type of action which was not witnessed by the reporter of an event. Presumably the reporter learned about the event by hearsay indicated by ‘apparently’ in (49). d. In the perfective series, the reciprocal/reflexive prefix e- marks transitive verbs, which is not expected because normally the transitivity marker is the prefix a-. Given these morphological and syntactic peculiarities of the Perfective series verbs, it can be argued that the iterated causative morpheme in Georgian and Mingrelian may be associated with two arguments, one who reports an event, and another, the causer of the same event. In addition, I suggest that these two events are morphologically realized by 34 See the introduction for the definition of these sets of person agreement prefixes (‘m-set’ and ‘v-set’) 100 the same VI. In Svan, the iteration occurs in unaccusative verbs, which are syntactically causativized. Presumably, the iteration was the reflex of syntactic causativization in Old Svan and in Proto-Kartvelian. However, the absence of ‘double’ causative meaning in Mingrelian and Georgian suggests that the reflex was lost sometime in the diachronic development of the Proto-language into the daughter languages and the second exponent of the causative morpheme was reanalyzed as a Perfective series marker. Thus, the iteration of a causative morpheme in the Perfective series has no longer been associated with the further causativization of the syntactic causative, but rather with some other functional head, whose exact identity is not our concern here, in this work, and will be explored in a separate article. 2.6 Adversity causatives in Georgian Pylkkanen (2002) argues that the introduction of a new syntactic argument is not a universal core property of causativization and that the basic distinguishing feature of causative verbs from their non-causative alternates is a syntactically implicit event argument ranging over the causing events. This means that all causative constructions involve CAUSE which combines with non-causative predicates and introduces a causing event to their semantics but does not necessarily introduce the external causer argument. This structural configuration is arguably present in Japanese adversity and Finnish desiderative causatives. Although both constructions lack the external argument, they have causative meaning and they presumably have some implicit causer argument, which is interpreted as an event itself. Due to such semantics of adversity causatives, Pylkkanen (2002) arrives at two possibilities in terms of CAUSE and Voice bundling across 101 languages. In the languages like Japanese and Finnish, where the CAUSE does not bundle with Voice, two configurations of causatives are possible: (41)a. Causative with an external argument VoiceP X 35 Voice’ Voice CAUSE-P CAUSE b. Unaccusative causative CAUSE-P CAUSE VP … (Pylkkanen 2002: 90) Pylkkanen’s main argument is that since some languages separate CAUSE from Voice, the strongest theory would maintain this separation universally, so that the CAUSE would never introduce an external argument. Stemming from these two possible structures for causatives, she presents two opposing views on their semantics reported in the literature. One view (Doron 1999) denies the existence of two event arguments and relates the external argument to the caused event via a causer theta-role (Pylkkanen 2002:79). Another, more traditional, view recognizes a relation between two events in the causative (Parsons 1990). Pylkkanen’s analysis is sympathetic to the latter. She refers to causatives as bi-eventive (bi-clausal) predicates. Doron’s view interprets causatives based on the thematic roles of arguments projected in these structures. Doron’s thematic role view does not allow for the possibility of causatives without external arguments and 35 It is assumed that X is either DP or NP in these constructions. 102 identifies the introduction of causative meaning with the introduction of an external argument. The bi-eventive analysis, by contrast, predicts the existence of causatives without an external argument such as those attested in Japanese adversity and Finnish desiderative causatives. Pylkkanen (2002, 2008) specifically shows that, in Japanese adversity causatives, it is possible to posit the existence of a causing event without relating any argument to it. Also there is a clear morphological distinction between the adversity passive and adversity causative structures. Here are some examples: (42) a. Adversity passive Taroo-ga musuko-ni sin-are-ta. Taroo-Nom son-Dat die-PASS-PAST ‘Taro’s son died on him.’ b. Adversity causative Taroo-ga musuko-ni Taroo-Nom son-Dat ‘Taro’s son died on him.’ sin-ase-ta. die-CAUS-PAST (Pylkkanen 2002: 82) Although the meanings of these two constructions resemble each other, they are not identical. (42a) can be interpreted as Taro’s son died without any particular cause, while (42b) attributes this death to some outside cause. In Georgian, adversity causatives with similar meaning are productive and show similar semantic properties to their Japanese counterparts in that the event expressed by the verb is caused by some external causer argument which is not projected in the structure and the dative causee argument acts out an event expressed by the verb: (43) Adversity causatives in Georgian 103 a. m- e 36k’vl- evin 371S- Voice- kill- CAUS‘I am caused to kill X’. eb- a TH- 3O/Ser b. metrevin1S- Voicedrag- CAUS‘I am caused to drag X.’ ebTH- c. m- eglejin1S- Voice- tearCAUS‘I am caused to tear X’. eb- a TH- 3O/Ser d. m- ebrdɣvevin1S- Voicetear.apart- CAUS‘I am caused to tear X apart.’ e. m- emasxara- v1S- Voicefoolinfn‘I am caused to fool X.’ f. m- elandʒ’ɣ- v1s- Voice- scold- infn‘I am caused to scold X.” a 3O/Ser eb- a TH- 3O/Ser eb- ineb- a TH- CAUS- TH- 3O/Ser ineb- a CAUS- TH- 3O/Ser The lack of the root-conditioned allomorphy of -in in (43) is similar to the cases previously discussed in this chapter. The idea is that CAUSE is an outer head and it is insulated from the root with the ‘doubled’ layer of bracketing. This is because the CAUSE in these structures selects for a vP complement whose head along with the category-defining head v insulates the root from the CAUSE. Even though these two heads are not phonologically realized, they still prevent Root-conditioned allomorphy of the morpheme inserted into the CAUSE. 36 Note that I am glossing the prefix e- as Voice because in these structures, because it does not mark the causative head. I assume that it is the part of the syncretism of Voice markers. 37 I am glossing –evin as a causative marker for convenience here assuming that –ev is a thematic suffix presumably inserted into the Infl0 or T0. See discussion below. 104 Another question is why the VI for the CAUSE –in is inserted in these structures, which are not obviously ditransitive (given the insertion context of this VI in (23)). The answer can be found in the interaction between the morphemes realizing various functional heads. As seen in (43), another exponent for the CAUSE, the affix a- is absent and this could be due to the different argument structure of these structures from the causatives discussed above. Since the causer argument is not projected this sets adversity causatives apart from other syntactic causatives discussed so far. Following Embick (1997) I argue that this is due to the [NonActive] feature on Voice and because of this feature, the zero elsewhere item for CAUSE is realized in the pre-base position-ofexponence (the 3rd slot) and the exponent of NonActive Voice can be inserted unobstructed. Since the affix –in is available as a primary exponent of CAUSE to be discharged in the post-base position, it will be realized in this slot in the absence of a- in the pre-base slot. This type of interaction between the exponents of Voice and the causative heads can be argued to be an instance of discontinuous feeding (Noyer 1997). As argued above, this mutual dependency of the VIs may be formalized one VI ‘conditioning’ the appearance of another VI in the same verb. Also it is evident that –evin in the above adversity causatives is inserted in syllabledefective roots where the latter contains just consonant clusters. As argued above in section 2.4, I assume that this –evin is a morphologically complex morpheme itself and that it consists of two VIs ev+in that are inserted for the thematic and causative morphemes respectively. As argued elsewhere in this chapter, CAUSE is an outer head while the thematic markers are often placeholder affixes. The insertion of the VI into the 105 node immediately adjacent to the root can be root-conditioned as argued in Embick (2009). I assume that this happens with the thematic affix –eb in the above adversity causatives. Thus, -eb/-ev insertion will be subject to Root conditioned allomorphy. (44) VIs for the non-cyclic head -ev/-eb / root[-]_____ - /elsewhere Now let’s expand a little bit on the prefix e- marking Voice in these structures. This exponent is multifunctional in Georgian showing the instances of syncretism across various classes of verbs. It can mark passive, certain two-place transitive verbs which I call ‘reciprocals’, and reflexive structures as well as certain types of applicatives, which will be discussed in detail in Chapter 3. (Also see Appendix 1 for detailed explanation of this syncretism). Here are some examples of the mentioned structures which show the syncretism of Voice morphology with adversity causatives in (43): (45) Verbs denoting reciprocal events 38 a. velap’arak’ebi 1S- voice- talk ‘I talk to X.’ b. v- ečxubebi 1S- voice- quarrel ‘I quarrel with X.’ c. v- ek’amat ebi 1S- voice- argue ‘I argue with X.’ (46) Passives 38 These two-place predicates are different from regular transitives in that they project non-case-alternating nominative subjects and dative objects in Georgian. In English, these dynamic verbs also involve prepositional objects, which sets them apart from transitive structures projecting accusative themes. 106 a. m- edʒ’ɣvneba 1S- voice- dedicate ‘I am dedicated X.’ b. m- eʒ’leva 1S- voice- give ‘I am given it.’ As seen above, e- shows up in a wide variety of structures including reciprocals and passives among others. I argue that e- is an exponent of Voice in all these structures and that Embick’s (1997) feature [NonActive] on Voice can account for the syncretism displayed in these examples. One might argue that action sentences realized with this morpheme are like deponents and their Voice head may be specified for the same feature [NonActive] as in passives. How this feature is implemented at the PF blocking the appearance of the VI realizing the CAUSE is discussed next. The Voice head in reciprocals does not participate in any syntactic alternation in syntax. Therefore, the voice morphology does not effect a syntactic change and this class of verbs is expected to be inherently specified for [NonActive], which is realized with the VI e- at the morphological structure (MS) 39. In passives, Voice is also specified for the same [NonActive] feature. However, the non-active morphology in passives effect the passive alternation and I assume that the 39 As a consequence of this feature on the Voice0 head, the latter does not project an external causer argument. Rather, the DPs projected with this head are assigned nominative case across the series much like those of unaccusative and inchoative verbs. They also behave like derived subjects since reciprocals cannot alternate with passives as shown in (57): (47) Passive of reciprocal events impossible: * Dato dalap’arak’ebul ikna Nanas mier. D-Nom spoken was N by. ‘Dato was talked to by Nana.’ 107 feature [NonActive] is also present in syntax driving A-movement of an internal argument to the subject position. In adversity causatives, the feature [NonActive] may be also argued to be specified in syntax since the argument structure of these constructions seems to be very much similar to that of passive constructions: there is no overt causer argument projected by the Voice0 head and passive alternation of these structures is impossible as shown in (47). Although the non-active morphology does not effect a syntactic alternation in these constructions, the feature still has to be present in syntax to ensure that the external argument is not projected by Voice0. This is why I suggest that the feature [NonActive] is present in the syntax of all these constructions. I hypothesized above that the null exponent for CAUSE in the pre-base position is due to the feature content on the Voice head. The CAUSE is realized with the null exponent in the pre-base position freeing up the slot for the VI of the Voice0. Thus, the morphological shape of adversity causatives in Georgian is correlated with the argument structure of the predicate and the feature content on the Voice0 head. Here is the structure showing the derivation of adversity causatives: (48) The structure of adversity causatives a. m- ek’vl- evineba 1S- voice- kill- CAUS- TH- 3O ‘Something causes me to kill him/her.’ 108 b. VoiceP -ext. Arg. Voice’ Voice0 [NONACTIVE] e- vP vP DPDAT causee VP DPNOM Affect.arg. v’ v0 CAUSE -in (evin) v0 V’ k’vl ‘kill’ Note that the nominative argument is interpreted as an affected argument. The causer argument is not overtly projected in these structures and it may be assumed to be implicit. Arguably this affected argument marked with the nominative case checks its nominative case against Tns since the dative case on the causee argument is inherent and does not intervene between the Tns and the affected argument to check the nominative. The CAUSE in these structures takes a vP complement rather than the VP as said above. However, this does not amount to the bi-eventive analysis of these causatives because arguably there is no causer argument projected in this structure and the causee and the affected argument are processed as if they belong to the same ‘clause’. This can be shown by the test of depictive modification in which the depictive phrase can modify the affected argument when it attaches before the verb as shown in (49a) while the lower modification of Dato is degraded as in (49b): (49) Depictive modification test a. dato-s ivane D-Dat I-Nom mtvral-i e-k’vle-evin-eba. drunk-Nom Voice-kill-CAUS- 109 ‘Dato is caused to kill Ivan drunk.’ b.?? dato-s ivane e-k’vlev-in-eba mtvrali. D-Dat I-Nom Voice-kill-CAUS- drunk ‘Dato is caused to kill Ivan drunk’. As seen from these structures, depictive modification of the affected argument is possible only when the depictive phrase is local to this argument while the lower modification of the same argument is degraded as seen in (49b). This illustrates that the mono-eventive analysis of adversity causatives is an option for these types of structures since there is just one attachment site for the depictive to occur. This could be taken as evidence for mono-eventiveness of adversity causatives. Note also that the causee and affected argument do not participate in a passive alternation and cannot occur with the by- phrase: (50) The passive and by- phrase of adversity causative impossible: a. * iremi monadires e-k’vl-evin-eb-a Deer-Nom hunter-Dat CAUS.to.kill ‘The deer is caused to be killed by the hunter.’ ikna. BE b. * iremi monadires e-k’vl-evin-eb-a dato-s mier. Deer-Nom hunter-Dat CAUS.to.kill D-Gen by ‘The deer is caused to be killed by the hunter with Dato’s interference.’ As seen in (50), neither the nominative affected argument, nor the dative causee can A- move to form the passive. Thus, adversity passives are different syntactically from these adversity causatives. The morphological similarity of adversity causatives with passives and reciprocals can be due to the feature content on the Voice0 head. The hypothetical [NonActive] feature may be responsible for the Voice syncretism in all these structures. 110 2.7 ‘Pretend’-type predicates and their causatives 2.7.0 Introduction This section discusses causative alternation of the complex predicates formed by the composition of the grammaticized light verb ‘pretend to be’ and the CAUSE resulting in the syntactic causative with make X pretend to be Adj/N meaning. With the projection of the external argument in the specifier of the VoiceP these structures resemble ‘reflexive’ unergative verbs, which are also formed via NI/AI (Noun Incorporation and Adjective Incorporation, respectively). Similar constructions are attested in various languages (Nahuatl, Hiaki) and they are considered as multi-headed complex verbs (Baker 1996). As seen in (51), the morphologically complex structure contains the matrix and the embedded verbs the latter being formed by the incorporation of a noun or an adjective (dead) into some verbal head. Baker (1996) argues that alternatively the matrix verb may have a ditransitivized reflexive form. In such cases the embedded verb is understood as active: (51) Complex predicate in Nahuatl: A:mo ni- c- nochīhua- ltoca Not 1sS- 3sO- 1REFL- make- NONACT- consider ‘I don’t pretend to have made it.’ (Launey 1981: 269-271) The meaning of ‘pretend to be’ may be also rendered with the grammaticalized suffix ‘consider’ as in the following structures: (52) Complex predicates formed with compounding in Nahuatl: ōni- c- mic- cātocaca PAST-1sS- 3sO- die- PART- consider- PAST/PERF ‘I had believed him dead.’ (Launey 1981:269-271) 111 The matrix verb may involve the epistemic verbs such as mati ‘know, consider’, and toca ‘believe, consider’. In Georgian, the related constructions grammaticalize only ‘pretend’ and the embedded verb is often derived via the incorporation of a noun or an adjective. Interestingly enough, the embedded verb has the reflexive frame in Georgian. 2.7.1 Derivation of ‘pretend’-type complex verbs The following examples show the morphological structure of ‘pretend’ verbs: (53) a. mo- v- imk’vdar- une prev- 1S- REFL- deadpretend- Aor ‘I pretended to be dead.’ (tavi) self b. mo- v- imdʒ’inar- e prev- 1S- REFL - sleeping- - pretend- Aor ‘I pretended to be sleeping.’ (tavi) self c. mo- v- igizhianprev- 1S- REFL- crazy.with‘I pretended to be crazy.’ d. mo- v- inaɣvlianprev- 1S- REFL- sad.with‘(I) pretended to be sad.’ e. mo- v- ik’at’une prev- 1S- REFL- catpretend- Aor ‘(I) pretended to be like a cat.’ e pretend- Aor e pretend- Aor (tavi) self (tavi) self (tavi) self Notice that the allomorphy -un/- is associated with the ‘pretend’ part of this predicate. The morpheme realizing ‘pretend’ is root-adjacent but its insertion may not be subject to root-conditioned allomorphy. The affix un- for Pretend0 is inserted in the forms with mono-syllabic complex roots, while the zero allomorph of ‘pretend’ shows up in 112 elsewhere contexts. Since the VIs for the Pretend0 are insulated from the Root with the derivational affixes it may be that these derivational affixes block the insertion of the VI un for Pretend0. Based on the data above I tentatively posit the environments for the insertion of VIs for Pretend0 as conditioned by the number of syllables in the Root + Derivational affix complex. When this complex is just mono-syllabic, the insertion of –un is not blocked, but when it exceeds this phonological shape, then the null exponent for Pretend is realized. Here are these items: (54) VIs for the ‘pretend’ head a. -un Pretend0 / root + Der. Affix = [] ______ b. - Pretend0 / elsewhere This evidence shows that the complex root containing the category-defining head may be still visible at the point when Pretend0 merges as the allomorphy of the latter is rootconditioned. This grammaticalized head Pretend0 is thus a non-cyclic element that can ‘see’ the root upon the merger. Notice also that the lexical V0 in these verbs is ‘complex’, in the sense that the root is accompanied by category-defining affixes: (55) Complex Vs of ‘pretend’-type predicates a. m-k’vd-ar der-die-der ‘Dead’ b. m-dʒ’in-ar der-sleep-der ‘Sleeping person’ c. gizh-ian crazy-der ‘With crazy’ d. č’k’v-ian smart-der ‘With smart’ e. naɣvl-ian sad-der ‘Sad’ 113 In these complex words, the category-defining morphemes merging with roots also have allomorphs (m--ar, -ian). Presumably, these derivational affixes categorize roots as adjectives or nouns (Aronson 1990). Following Embick (2009), I assume that these category-defining heads are cyclic but they may not prevent the root-conditioned allomorphy of outer non-cyclic heads such as Pretend0. The relevant evidence will be presented after the structure of these complex words in (53)–(54) is shown: (56) Complex Vs in ‘pretend’-type predicate a. m-k’vd-ar-(i) der-die-der 40- (Nom) ‘Dead’ b. k’vd ‘dead’ a/n m-/-ar (57) Complex Vs in ‘pretend’-type predicate a. gizh-ian- (i) crazy-der (Nom) ‘Crazy.with’ b. gizh a ‘crazy’ -ian Furthermore, I assume that the reflexive Voice is merged in these structures whose head is realized with the prefix i-. This prefix also marks reflexive applicatives 41 and there is a notable pattern of syncretism of this marker across various classes of verbs including other reflexive verbs, which denote events directed to the body parts such as 40 The VIs inserted in the category-defining heads such as a or n are glossed as derivational because these affixes are highly idiosyncratic occurring with the particular stems. There are many such affixes in Georgian but the roots in ‘pretend-type’ predicates use only a few of them. 41 The derivation of the structures with reflexive applicative markers will be discussed in the next chapter. 114 comb, shave, passives, etc. 42 There is no evidence that root-conditioned allomorphy is associated with this VI (the affix i-) though. This is perhaps due to the fact that Voice is an outer cyclic head or it merges above vP whose head is cyclic. Thus, the lower portion of the complex verb including grammaticalized ‘Pretend’ is not visible to the functional heads merged later in the derivation. See also Appendix A for the syncretism associated with the affix i- as the reflexive Voice marker. The structure of ‘Pretend’ predicates may be sketched the following way: (58) ‘Pretend’ -type predicate a. mo- v- imk’vdar- une prev-1S- REFL- deadpretend- Aor ‘I pretended to be dead.’ b. VoiceP DPNOM/ERG Voice’ vP v0 PretendP Pretend0 -un/- VP DPACC self VoiceREFL i- - V’ Adj/NP V0 - k’vd a/n ‘dead’ m-/-ar, -ian I assume that the Root first is merged with n or a categorizing head and then this structure is again categorized as a verb with the verbalizer v0. Apparently, the inner category-defining head a or n is not a cyclic head and does not send the structure off for LF/PF processing, since the functional head Pretend0 merged above these categorizing 42 I will not go into the details of this syncretism as it is irrelevant for the present purposes. 115 elements is still sensitive to the properties of Roots plus the derivational elements. Recall that this was a property of non-cyclic heads as argued in the introduction in the discussion on Embick (2009). Note that the affix realizing the reflexive Voice is inserted into the slot of argument structure-changing morphemes and the verb incorporates into it after the event-introducing v0 head which verbalizes the assembled structure. 2.7.2 Causative alternation of ‘pretend’-type verbs CAUSE takes a complete vP, with all its arguments, as its complement. The morphological shape of these causatives resembles those of make X do V syntactic causatives of unergative and transitive verbs where the affixes a- and –in are present as the phonological exponents of two CAUSEs since in addition to the transitive structure of the Pretend-type predicate with its implicit ‘self’ argument, the causee argument is also projected in this structure. I assume that this is expected given the [+ ditrans] feature on v0 head. First observe the empirical base of causatives formed from such predicates: (59) Causative alternates of ‘pretend’ type predicates a. v- amk’vdar- uneb- ineb 1S- CAUS- deadpretend- TH- CAUS- TH ‘I caused X to pretend to be dead.’ b. vamdʒ’inar- eb- ineb 1S- CAUS- sleepingTH- CAUS- TH ‘I caused X to pretend to be asleep.’ c. v- agizhianeb- ineb 1S- CAUS- crazy.with- TH- CAUS- TH ‘I caused X to pretend to be crazy.’ d. v- ak’at’- uneb- ineb 1S- CAUS- cat- pretend- TH- CAUS- TH ‘I caused X to pretend to be a cat-like.’ 116 The argument structure of ‘pretend’-type causatives includes the causer argument, which is projected by the active Voice0 (marked with nom/erg/dative cases across the series). The causee is presumably projected by the vP complement that the lower CAUSE selects and is marked with the dative case. There is a sense that the anaphoric argument is also projected in the structure, interpreted as self as in (53). As suggested in (23), the VIs for CAUSE in such constructions containing both a- and –in exponents may be analyzed as realizing two separate causative heads. The argument case-marking follows a monoclausal pattern. CAUSE is not subject to the root-conditioned allomorphy presumably because it is insulated from the root with double-bracketing: (60) Causative of ‘pretend’-type predicate a. v- amk’vdar- uneb- ineb 1S- CAUS- deadpretend- TH- CAUS- TH ‘I cause X to pretend to be dead.’ 117 b. VoiceP DPNOM/ERG causer Voice’ vP vP vP CAUSE1 a- v0 PretendP VP DPACC ‘self’ k’vd ‘dead’ V0 Voice0 CAUSE2 -in Pretend0 un/- a, n m-ar -ian Note that in (60b) the arrows do not indicate the order of linearization applying to the morphemes realizing the relevant functional and lexical heads in this complex structure. It is assumed that the post-syntactic pre-insertion rules modify this order which will not be discussed here. We can use adverbial, negation scope tests to establish the complex syntactic structure of the causative forms derived from pretend-type predicates. These tests illustrate that VP-modifying adverbials can scope over both the causing and the resulting event. A negative marker should also do the same depending on the attachment site, low or high: (61) VP-modifying adverbial test a. datom D-Erg gia-s G-Dat tavi self mo- amk’vdarun- eb- ina prev-CAUS-dead.pretend-TH- CAUS- 3S 118 isev. again ‘Dato caused Gia to pretend to be dead again.’ b. datom D gias G tavi self isev mo- amk’vdarun- eb- in- a again prev-CAUS-dead.pretend-TH-CAUS- 3S In (61a), the adverbial modifier scopes over the causing event carried out by Dato while in (62b) it modifies the event carried out by the agentive causee Gia. This means that the structure is internally complex and the adverbial ‘again’ (isev) modifies two separate events. Thus the structure can be considered as bi-eventive. The following test employing the placement of negative marker with respect to the causee argument also shows the similar bi-eventive properties of these constructions: (63) Negation test a. dato-m gia-s tavi ar mo- agizhianeb- ina. D-Erg G-Dat self not prev-CAUS-crazyCAUS‘Dato cause Gia not to pretend to be crazy.’ b. dato-m ar mo-a-gizhianeb- ina D-Erg not -CAUS-crazy- CAUS‘Dato did not cause Gia to pretend to be crazy.’ gia-s G-Dat tavi. self The negative marker (ar) can either modify the causing event (the matrix verb) or the caused event (the embedded one). Georgian is Low-attachment language for the NegP and this means that Neg head cannot scope over the entire clause. We find two kinds of readings for each of these structures: 1) Dato did not cause Gia to pretend as if he is crazy, and 2) Dato caused Gia not to pretend to be crazy, I will conclude that the 119 causative structures (as evidenced with the Negation test) are complex syntactically and that word formation parallels the syntactic derivation 43. 2.8 Psych verbs and causative alternation 2.8.0 The empirical base of state, dynamic passive, and activity psych verbs In Georgian and the related languages Mingrelian and Svan, three types of psychverbs emerge in terms of morpho-semantics: state, dynamic passive, and activities (following Aronson 1990). In what follows, I will assume that state psych verbs express ‘non-core’ events in the sense of Tenny (2000), which essentially are stative eventualities, while dynamic passives and activity verbs express non-stative events (Bach 1986). These three classes show a differential ability to alternate with causatives and passives, namely, only activity psych verbs can do both. Here are some examples: (64) State psych verbs a. m- iq’var- s 44 1S- applic - love- 3O ‘I love X.’ b. m- ʒ’ul- s 1S- hate- 3O ‘I hate X.’ 43 It should be mentioned though that the Negation test is not as robust as other relevant tests used above because Georgian is a non-strict Negative concord language (Haegemann 2006, Zejistra 2005) and in a number of cases (such as one containing several negative words—nobody never cause nobody to do nothing) the negative marker is not required to precede the verb and is dropped. Often such languages do not have Negative Polarity Items (NPI) like English. Due to these properties it can be argued that the negation test can work with the sentences without multiple negation words in Negative concord languages. 44 The applicative morpheme in this verb does not have the same semantics as it would have in the transitive counterpart and in the traditional literature it is referred to as the version marker. In the following transitive applicative structure I build the house for myself (a-v-i-shen-e) the prefix i- clearly has an applicative meaning while in the above structure ‘I love’ it does not. However, we gloss this morpheme as applicative and in Chapter 3 of this dissertation, I will argue that it realizes the high Appl0 head in psychological predicates. 120 c. m- eshin- i1S- voice- afraid- TH‘I am afraid of X.’ a 3O d. mo- m- c’on- s 45 prev- 1S- like- 3O ‘I like X.’ e. m- ezizɣ- eb- a 1S- voice- loath- TH- 3O ‘I loath something.’ f. m- enat’r- eb- a 1S- voice- miss- TH- 3O ‘I miss X.’ g. m- examusheb- a 1S- voice- discomfort- TH- 3O ‘I am not comfortable with X.’ The state psych verbs in (64) project dative-marked experiencer arguments, which are interpreted as non-voluntary subjects. Experiencer arguments trigger the inverse agreement pattern (generally associated with dative subjects and spelled out as m-set markers on verbs) 46. Next, consider dynamic passives: (65) Dynamic passives a. m- iq’var- deb- a 1S- applic- love- pass- TH- 3O ‘I am falling in love with X’. b. m- dʒ’ul- deb- a 1S- hate pass- TH- 3O ‘I am becoming hateful of X.’ 45 Note that only (64d) is marked with the preverbal morpheme, which generally marks aspect on verbs. The VI mo- does not have any function in this form because statives usually do not express achievements or perfective events as argued by many (Tenny 2000). It is inserted for morphological well-formedness. The realization of other morphemes in the set (e-, i- and - ) also depends on language-specific readjustment rules operating in the post-syntactic component and we do not discuss them here as they are irrelevant for present purposes. 46 See Introduction of the dissertation for discussion on the agreement patterns in Georgian. 121 c. m- zizɣdeb- a 1S- loath- pass- TH- 3O ‘I am becoming *loathful of X.’. d. misc’ordeba 1S- applic- straighten- pass- TH- 3O ‘I enjoy X.’ 47 Dynamic passives also contain the inverse person agreement markers (m-set) which index dative experiencers much like in states shown in (64). Another common syntactic property that dynamic passives share with states is that they cannot alternate with causatives, i.e. these structures cannot add the causer argument: (66) a. State verbs cannot causativize: * m- aq’var- s 1S- CAUS- love- 3O ‘I am caused to love X’ b. Dynamic passives cannot causativize: *m- aq’var- d- eb- a 1S- CAUS- lovepass- TH- 3O ‘I am caused to fall in love with X.’ It is also notable that states and dynamic passives have the same applicative marker i-/u-, which is sensitive to the person feature of the dative experiencer: [+ participant] experiencers are marked with the affix i- while [-participant] ones with u-: (67) States a. m- iq’var- s 1S- applic- love- 3O/pres ‘I love X.’ b. g- iq’var- s 2S- applic- love- 3O/pres 47 The form in (79d) is interpreted idiomatically, as the root has a different meaning (straighten) from the resulting predicate (enjoy). 122 ‘You love X.’ c. uq’varapplic- love‘He loves X.’ s 3O/pres (68) Dynamic passives a. m- iq’var- deb- a 1S- applic- love- PASS- TH- 3O/pres ‘I am falling in love with X.’ b. g- iq’var- deb- a 2S- applic- love- PASS- TH- 3O/pres ‘You are falling in love with X.’ c. uq’var- deb- a applic- love- PASS- TH- 3O/pres ‘He is falling in love with X.’ Observe that the morphological shape of the activity verbs is quite different from the above two classes. In what follows first I present the examples of activity psych verbs followed by the analysis of the morphological make-up of these verbs: (69) Activity psych verbs a. v- iq’var- eb 1S- REFL- love- TH ‘I am loving X.’ b. v- idʒ’ul- eb 1S- REFL- hate- TH ‘I am hating X.’ c. v- ic’on- eb 1S- REFL- like- TH ‘I am liking X.’ d. v- izizɣ- eb 1S- REFL- loath- TH ‘I am loathing X.’. 123 e. v- inat’r- eb 1S- REFL- dream- TH ‘I will dream about X.’ Experiencer arguments of activities are marked with nom/erg/dative cases across the series and the Case features are checked by the Voice0 head (and like external arguments of transitive verbs they trigger the basic pattern of agreement that is spelled out as v-set). Presumably, the surface position of experiencers in activities is different from that of the dative arguments of dynamic passives and states. In the analysis of these classes, I will argue below that the dative experiencers are projected by a different functional head than the nom/erg/dative arguments of activities. Another difference between activities and the other two classes is that the prefix i- in activities is not sensitive to the person feature of the experiencer argument as in states and dynamic passives shown in (67)-(68). Following Aronson (1990), I interpret this morpheme as the marker of the Reflexive Voice0 head, which merges in various two-place reflexive verbs to express events directed to one’s own body parts (shave, wash, comb, braid, etc.) and also, in some applicative structures, to express the progressive possession meaning 48. In psychological verbs this meaning is absent though. Here are the examples showing that the VI i-, which is not sensitive to the person features of the external argument, is present in activity psych verbs: (70) Activities a. v- iq’var- eb 1S- REFL- love- TH 48 In this dissertation I follow Pylkkanen (2002) in classification of applicatives into high and low structures based on the attachment site of the ApplP. See chapter 3 for detailed discussion of these and reflexive applicatives. 124 ‘I am loving X.’ b. iq’var- eb REFL- love- TH ‘You are loving X.’ c. iq’var- eb- s REFL- love- TH- 3O/pres ‘He/she is loving X.’ Another observation about the three types of psych predicates is that only activities alternate with causatives and passives. They may have so called reflexive and nonreflexive causative alternates. The latter are interpreted as syntactic causatives with makes X love… Y meaning in which CAUSE is marked with the a- and –in exponents, while reflexive causatives are interpreted as make X love… self. These are marked just with the affix a-. Observe the data in the following: (71) Non-reflexive causatives of activity psych verbs a. v- aq’var- eb- in1S- CAUS- love- TH- CAUS‘I caused X to love Y.’ eb TH b. v- adʒ’ul- ebineb 1S- CAUS- hate- TH- CAUS- TH ‘I caused X to hate Y.’ c. v- ac’oneb- ineb 1S- CAUS- like/approve- TH- CAUS- TH ‘I caused X to like/approve Y’. d. vazizɣ- eb- ineb 1S- CAUS- loath- TH- CAUS- TH ‘I caused X to loath Y.’ (72) Reflexive causatives of activity psych verbs a. v- aq’var- eb 1S- CAUS- love- TH 125 ‘I am causing X to love (me).’ b. v- adʒ’ul- eb 1S- CAUS- hate- TH ‘I am causing X to hate (me).’ c. vac’oneb 1S- CAUS- like/approve- TH ‘I am causing X to like (me).’ d. v- azizɣ- eb 1S- CAUS- loath- TH ‘I causing X to loath (me).’ Notice that the morphological shape of reflexive causatives is similar to that of causatives derived from inchoative verbs. Activities also alternate with passives as expected and this is shown in the following example: (73) Passive of activities Bavshvi she- q’var- eb- ul- i- a Child prev- love- TH- der- TH- BE ‘The child is loved (by X).’ As seen in (71)-(72), activities alternate with passives and causatives. This syntactic property can be associated with transitive eventful structures. Thus, activities crucially differ from dynamic passives and states with their syntax and morphology as well. It is also of interest to note that psych verbs in Svan come into two semantic varieties of stative and activity verbs like in Georgian: (74) State and activities in Svan Lentex dialect a. xalät’ ‘he loves’ 49 b. ilat’- une applic-love- CAUS-tense ‘He is falling in love.’ (Topuria 1967: 235) 49 Note that the glossing of these forms is mine (L. L while the forms are taken from the mentioned source verbatim) 126 When the activity psych verb is causativized the suffix –en/-ûn is added to the reduced root: (75) Causatives of psych verbs: a. ilat’- ûne Upper Svan dialect applic- love- CAUS- Tns ‘He is falling in love.’ b. xalat’- ûne 50 pers - CAUS- love- CAUS- Tns ‘He is causing X to love him.’ c. ilt’- une intrans- love- CAUS- Tns ‘He is falling in love.’ d. xalt’eni pers- CAUS- love- CAUS- TH ‘He is causing Y to love him.’ (75a & c) are the non-causative forms of two semantic types of psych verbs. (75b & d) represent their causative counterparts. Note that the suffix –un/-en marks the reflexive causative. Based on this limited data it is still possible to conclude that in Svan, the causative homologue of Georgian –in/-evin is inserted even in activity psych verbs whose meaning is not determined by the causative morpheme. 51 The morphosyntactic analysis of the three types of psych verbs is presented next. 2.8.1 Analysis of the morphosyntax of the three classes of psych verbs and their causatives 50 We gloss person agreement markers in these verbs with the pers since their exact reference is not important for our analysis here. See appendix 2 for exact meanings of these glosses. 51 I speculated that since only activity psych verbs alternate with causatives, in Proto-Kartvelian (the mother tongue of Kartvelian languages) this –en/ûn could have been present and it may have been kept in Svan because this is the most archaic language of the South Caucasian language family. The same morpheme in Georgian has disappeared through diachronic development. 127 I propose that the morphosyntactic properties of the three classes of psych verbs may be analyzed in terms of the feature content and the selectional properties of the Voice0 head, which selects different complements in these three structures. In states and dynamic passives, dative experiencer arguments are interpreted as involuntary, non-instigator subjects (Mithun 1986), which trigger the inverse agreement (‘m-set’) on verbs illustrated in (64)-(65). These properties are presumably associated with the lower structural position of dative arguments. Specifically, I argue that the structural position of dative Experiencers in states and dynamic passives is the specifier of high ApplP and this case is presumably checked against the Appl0. However, in activities, the position of the external argument is in the specifier of the reflexive Voice0, which is realized with the exponent i-. The relevant question is which functional head in dynamic passives is marked with the suffix –d. Following Embick (1997), I assume that this morpheme may be associated with the [Passive] feature on the Voice0 head. Note also that states and dynamic passives have dative subjects projected by the high Appl0 head. The high ApplP presumably is selected by the Voice0 head which bears different feature than the Voice0 head in activities, since the latter projects the external argument. Given these structural differences, I argue that the Voice0 head in states and dynamic passives bears a feature which I tentatively call [NonActive] which is the same feature as argued to exist in adversity causatives above. NonActive Voice0 head selects for the ApplP. The morphological realization of [NonActive] may be zero, since in the position where the Voice0 is realized the applicative marker i-/u- shows up. I propose that the applicative 128 marker blocks the insertion of the VI for the non-active Voice both in states and dynamic passives. Therefore, this non-active Voice feature may be realized with e- or null elsewhere item. As opposed to these two classes, I argue that the Voice0 in activities is specified for the [+ Refl] feature, which is realized with the affix i- in all three persons. Observe the feature content on Voice0 in all three structures: (76) The feature specification on Voice0: a. States [+ NonActive] b. Dynamic passives [+ NonActive] [Passive] c. Activities [+ Refl] It is evident that the feature [Passive] is realized in the post-base position because the VI for this feature is not blocked by any other VI in this post-base slot. Another conclusion that we can draw based on the morphological shape of these causatives is that the VIs inserted into these different functional heads such as Voice and Appl0 realized in the pre-base slot can be represented with a hierarchy within a rule block for the terminal node (Halle & Marantz 1993 and others) in which the higher item with more specific features wins over the lower listed items for the insertion in this slot. From the data above, it was shown that the reflexive Voice beats the VI for the applicative in active structures and the latter beats nonactive Voice exponent in states and dynamic passives. Thus, the rule block for the realization of this slot in all three classes of psychological predicates exhibits the following ordering: (77) The rule block accounting for the insertion of VIs in the third slot 129 a. i- VoiceREFL / Class 1 52 b. i- Appl0 / [Dat] [+1], [+2] c. u- Appl0 / [Dat] [+3] d. e- VoiceNONACTIVE e. - elsewhere Based on this rule block the items listed higher will be inserted first into the third position of the template in these psych verbs and the higher listed item will win over the lower ones. Now the syntactic structure of states and dynamic passives may be presented in the following tree in (86c): (78) State a. m- iq’var- s 1S-applic-love- 3O/pres ‘I love X.’ Dynamic passive b. m- iq’var- deb- a 1S-applic- love- pass- TH- 3O/pres ‘I fall in love with X.’ c. The tree for states and dynamic passives TP vP v0 m- ApplP Appl’ DPDAT Appl0 i-/u- VP DPNOM Theme 52 T0 -s,-a,.. V’ V0 q’var ‘love’ I assume that the Class 1 is represented with the activities. 130 As opposed to states and dynamic passives, the reflexive Voice head in activities with its [Refl] features projects an external experiencer/agent argument. This construction can alternate with passives and causatives. The derivation of activity psych verbs can be sketched in the following: (79) Activities a. v- iq’var- eb 1S- REFL- love- TH ‘I am loving X.’ b. VoicePREFL DPNOM/ERG Voice’ Ext. Arg. vPDO VoiceREFL iVP v0 DPACC theme q’var ‘love’ Now the analysis for non-reflexive and reflexive causatives of psych verbs is presented. In reflexive causatives, the external argument causer and the theme are coreferential, while in non-reflexives, they are not. I argue that due to the presence of reflexive Voice, an empty argument PRO is projected in the specifier of VP and it is controlled from the external argument. The causer and the causee arguments are projected due to Voice and the vP complement that the CAUSE selects for in these structures. It is expected that the root-conditioned allomorphy associated with the CAUSE may not be an option in these verbs: (80) Reflexive causative of activities: 131 a. v- aq’var- eb 1S-CAUS- love- TH ‘I make X love me.’ b. VoiceP DPNOM/ERGi Voice’ external arg. causer vP Voice0 vP v0 CAUSE DPDAT v’ acausee VP v0 PROi V0 q’var ‘love’ The structure for the non-reflexive causative with no anaphoric causee argument may be assumed to contain two CAUSEs and the lower one takes an argument-full vP as its complement: (81) Non-reflexive causative of the activity psych verb b. a. v- aq’var- eb- ineb 1S- CAUS- love- TH- CAUS- TH ‘I make X fall in love with Y.’ VoiceP DPNOM/ERG Voice’ Ext.arg. vP Voice0 vP v0 CAUSE2 vP v0 -in CAUSE1 VP v0 aDPACC V0 theme q’var ‘love’ 132 The structural difference between reflexive and non-reflexive causative structures is that in the former, the theme and the causer external argument are co-referential and this can be interpreted as transitive structure conditioning the insertion of only a- into the CAUSE. The morphology therefore resembles that of causatives formed from inchoatives and generally, two-place predicates as shown above. Non-reflexive causatives clearly are ditransitive because co-reference between the causer and the theme is not present. It can be argued that the morphological marking of these causatives again reflects the argument structure of these predicates with two CAUSEs introduced in it. Thus, the feature specifications on the Voice0 head and the ability of these constructions to add the causer argument account for the absence of causative alternates in states and dynamic passives. Since states are non-eventive predicates (Bach 1986), they are unable to add the causer to the structure, while dynamic passives denote the type of events that cannot add the causer due to the [passive] feature on Voice. Thus the features of main functional projections above the root determine the argument structure of these verbs and the morphological marking of these heads is consistent with these features. 2.9 Causative predicates in related languages (Mingrelian and Svan) Mingrelian/Laz and Svan, the two languages spoken in the western part of Georgia, display similar causative constructions to Georgian. 2.9.0 The causative alternation in Svan The material for this section came from V. Topuria’s (1931, 1967) text on Svan. Topuria classifies verbs into two general classes of intransitives and transitives. As the 133 author notes, most of the intransitives can be transitivized in all three dialects of Svan. I will interpret this alternation broadly as a causative alternation or applicativization as shown in the following: (82) Intransitive a. xug (I am standing) Transitive b. m-īg (it is standing for me) c. m-ag (It is standing on me). The transitive verbs with two different morphological shapes in (80) are attested in two dialects: (80b) in Bal-Zemouri and (80c) in Lentex dialects. This alternation between inchoative/transitive pairs presumably involves causation as well. Based on the forms in (82)-(83), it is evident that inchoative-causative alternation is attested in Svan and is marked with the elsewhere prefix a- much like in Georgian: (83) Zemo-Svan dialect a. mi xû-a-k’re I open (it/them) b. si you c. edʒ-a he/she x-a-k’re open (it/them) a-k’re opens (it/them) Lashx dialect xû-a-k’ren open (it/them) x-a-k’reni “ a-k’reni “ Lentex dialect xû-a-k’äre open (it/them) x-a-k’äre “ a-k’äre “ Notice that in the absence of preverbal morphemes (which in Svan marks the aspect) only person agreement and valency-changing morphemes precede the verbal base in (78). After excluding 1-2 person subject agreement morphemes the root (k’re) and the causative marker a- can be separated from these forms. Topuria notes that a more typical causative morpheme in Svan is the suffix –un. This marks the syntactic causative of make X do V type: (84) Svan causatives 134 a. xašx- une burn- CAUS- Tns ‘X causes Y to burn Z.’ b. xak’r- une open- CAUS- Tns ‘X causes Y to open the door.’ c. xat’x- une return- CAUS- Tns ‘X makes Y to return Z.’ This suffix is common in the Lashx dialect, while in the Zemo-Bal dialect al-ûn-e or a-ûn-e and its phonological allomorphs may be inserted in CAUSE. The Georgian causative prefix a- appears to be related to it. Some further evidence is presented next: (85) Intransitive a. iûʒ- e intrans-sleep-Tns ‘He is sleeping.’ Causative b. aûʒune CAUS- sleep- CAUS- Tns *‘He sleeps X.’ c. izg- e intrans-live- Tns ‘He lives.’ d. ä/azg- une CAUS- live- CAUS- Tns ‘He/she settles X down.’ e. ičexû intrans-graze ‘(A cow) grazes.’ f. äčxune CAUS- graze- CAUS- Tns ‘He/she lets (cows) to graze.’ g. ʒecx- n- i wake-tense-TH ‘X is awakening.’ h. äʒcxune CAUS- wake- CAUS- Tns ‘X causes Y to awake.’ Note that the exponents ä(a)- and -un of the causative head is also found in Svan. This is similar to Georgian a- and -evin(-in) marking in the causative alternates of transitive verbs and ‘pretend’-type predicates. The causative of unergative verbs in Svan also has the same marker, which corresponds to the projection of the causer and the causee arguments yielding transitive structure. The same morphological reflex is present 135 in Georgian when complex bi-eventive structures are projected for the syntactic causatives of various classes of verbs. In the Russian synopsis of the Svan grammar, Topuria (1967) describes the causative formation rule which entails –e /–i deletion with –un suffixation. The latter suffix can be preceded by –al or –ä (in High Bahl dialect), which marks repeated events, and in Low Bahl and Lent’ex dialects, by –al or –a, etc. (Topuria 1967:286). These affixes may be followed by –ûn/-un. Sometimes these suffixes may be lost such as in the Low Bahl dialect shown in (84b): (86) Causatives of transitives in Svan High Bahl a. xamārā/ûne xamaräûne forces to prepare/cook something Low Bahl b. xamaralne c. xamārune xamārûne The same –un marks the causatives of the unaccusative verbs such as sleep: (87) Transitives in Svan a. iûʒe a-ûʒune sleeps ‘X causes Y to sleep’ b. aq’ure aq’ûne ‘X lies’ X lies Y down It can be argued that in many respects the causatives of various classes of verbs in Svan are very much similar to those in Georgian. The causatives of inchoative and transitive verbs may be marked with the suffix –un which is the phonological homologue of the Georgian affix –in. The limited data suggests that the variety of verb classes that causativize in this language is almost the same as in Georgian as the limited data suggests. 136 2.9.1 Causative alternation in Mingrelian Kajaia’s (2001) Mingrelian-Georgian dictionary is used as my primary source here. This book also contains some discussion of causativization. Causatives in Mingrelian can be formed from the Aorist screeve by adding the –ap-u suffix. Here are some examples (Kajaia 2001:58): Table 5. The transitive and causative predicates in Mingrelian Infinitive a. č’ar-u-a write-infix-infin To write b. tol-u-a c. zal-a d. č’al-a e. txu-al-a To peel To mix dough To sew To ask for Aorist causative ‘Cause X to write’ o-č’ar-ap-(u)- u prev-write-causscrv ‘Cause X to peel’ o-tol-ap-u- u ‘Cause X to mix’ o-z-ap-u- u ‘Cause X to sew’ o-č’-ap-u- u ‘Cause X to ask for’ o-txu-ap-u- u These examples show that in the Aorist screeve –apu is immediately adjacent to the root which may or may not be reduced (such as in (86d)). Thus no morphology interferes between the root and the causative suffix. I suggest that that the CAUSE takes the phase complement (vP) in these causative structures of inchoatives and this explains the absence of idiomatic readings for all these forms. The morphological structure of causatives in these examples is almost the same as in corresponding Georgian counterparts in the Aorist screeve. The only difference between the Georgian syntactic causatives of make X do V type and the Mingrelian counterparts listed in Table 5 is the absence of the homologous causative marker in Mingrelian. Compare the following Georgian causatives to those above: (88) Transitive verbs and their causative alternates in Georgian 137 Infinitive Aorist causative a. c’er-a write-INF ‘to write’ da- ac’er- ina Prev-CAUS- write- CAUS- Aor ‘Cause X to write’ b. prckvn-a peel-INF ‘to peel’ da- aprckvn- evin- a Prev-CAUS- peel- CAUS-Aor ‘Cause X to peel’ c. zel-v-a mix-infix-INF ‘to mix the dough’ mo- azel- vina Prev-CAUS-mix- INF- CAUS- Aor ‘Cause X to mix the dough’ d. k’er-v-a sew-infix-INF ‘to sew’ she- ak’er- vina Prev- CAUS- sew- INF- CAUS-Aor ‘Cause X to sew’ e. txovn-a ask-INF ‘to ask/request’ a- txovnina Prev- request- CAUS- Aor ‘Cause X to request Z.’ In Georgian, both the prefix a- and the suffix –in/-evin are inserted as VIs for the causative head in the syntactic causative. As seen in (88), the VIs inserted into the CAUSE are not sensitive to the morphophonological properties of roots. This may be expected given the uniform syntactic structure of these causatives across these languages. As for the Mingrelian examples in Table 7, I attribute the loss of causative prefix to diachronic development, assuming that in Proto-Kartvelian the prefix a- was present based on the data of Georgian and Svan causatives. The empirical evidence from the three languages shows the similar morphological shape of causative predicates and almost all classes of verbs can participate in causative alternation. It thus seems reasonable to assume that Mingrelian and Svan causatives show the same syntactic 138 properties in terms of bi-clausal/bi-eventive behavior. This requires further empirical verification with native speakers. 2.10 Conclusions The chapter showed empirical evidence of causative constructions in three related languages: Georgian, Mingrelian, and Svan and argued that they display common morphological properties of lexical and syntactic causatives formed from inchoative, unergative, transitive and other classes of verbs. The inchoative/causative alternation is both morphologically and syntactically distinct from the make X do V causative alternation in these languages. This suggests that morphology is consistent with the syntax of these constructions. Specifically, the prefix a- inserted into the causative head in inchoative causatives ‘signals’ the feature [trans] of the vP and correspondingly, the causer and theme or the causer and the causee arguments are projected into the structure, while the additional marker for CAUSE -in is inserted in iterated causatives of unergative, transitive and other types of verbs, which presumably aligns with the ditransitive structure, combining the causer, the causee(s), and the theme arguments. Table 8 below summarizes the morphological marking of these constructions by the class of verbs: 139 Table 6. The morphological marking of causatives of various verb classes CAUSATIVE Inchoatives Unaccusatives Unergatives aBake, open, break, etc. Roll, cool, warm up, etc. Sing, scream, cough, laugh,... Transitives ‘Pretend’-type predicates Psychological verbs (reflexive) Psychological verbs (non-reflexive) VIs for CAUSE a-/ -in Sow, make, eat, etc. Pretend to die, pretend to sleep, etc. X makes Y love X, X makes Y hate X, etc. X makes Y love Z, X makes Y hate Z, etc. The distinct morphological shape of syntactic causatives is also associated with the syntactic behavior of the mentioned causatives in terms of VP-modifying adverbials, adjunct control and other syntactic tests, which show that make X do V causatives are complex syntactically. Two different meanings are interpreted in the clauses where the adverbial scopes over the event performed by the causer and the causee. The adverbials in the causatives of inchoative verbs do not show such bi-eventive properties. Similarly, the test of depictive modification applied to lexical and syntactic causatives has also shown that the former have mono-eventive properties since only agentive modification is allowed while X makes Y do V causatives display bi-eventive through the depictive modification of both the causer and the causee arguments. The chapter has illustrated, however, that the case-marking of the causer and the causee follows the mono-clausal pattern and that these arguments are marked in a way that shows they are projected in the same clause. 140 Another result of the research on causative constructions showed that the Vocabulary Items for the causative head may be homophonous across different classes of verbs but these items are different with their insertion contexts and distribution. For example, the phonological exponent a- inserted into the CAUSE of lexical causatives is sensitive to the root properties while the same phonological exponent in X makes Y do V causatives is sensitive to the [trans] feature of v0 merged in these structures. The research has also found that the double marking of the causative head in syntactic causatives is the natural consequence of two CAUSE heads merged in these types of structures. Such transparent correlation between the syntactic heads and their morphological realization is of interest given a wide distribution of null exponents as default markers of different functional heads in this language. These findings on the interaction of the functional morphology with the argument structure and generally, the syntax of causative constructions will be further examined in the larger context of applicative constructions in the three related languages, which is explored next. 141 CHAPTER 3 APPLICATIVES AS COMPLEX PREDICATES 3.0 Introduction The chapter explores the morphosyntactic properties of applicative constructions in three languages: Georgian, Mingrelian, and Svan in which the Applicative head (Appl0) is marked morphologically. The main goal of this research is to identify the syntactic and morpho-phonological rules whose interaction determines the morphological shape and associated meaning of these constructions. Since all three languages under investigation are polysynthetic, a particular emphasis is placed on the morphological realization of applicative heads in various syntactic contexts and the interaction of the applicative morphology with other argument structure-changing morphemes. 3.1 Theoretical goals 3.1.0 Outline of the chapter The goal of the chapter is to come up with a unified theory of how the meaning and the morphological structure of applicatives are derived in syntax in Georgian, Mingrelian, and Svan. The theoretical premise that underlies this goal is that the morphological realization of the Appl0 head may not be uniform across various syntactic contexts and may be subject to contextual allomorphy. Sometimes the applicative relations may be expressed not by the specialized Appl0 head but by another functional projection. There are also cases where the Appl0 head is not morphologically realized but the low 142 applicative meaning is still present 53. Therefore, this chapter aims to explore the role of various rules and principles of Distributed Morphology (DM) with regard to the interface between the syntactic-semantic and morphological components for a better understanding of where the above relations between arguments come from in the absence of applicative morphology. The ancillary goal of this research is to find out whether the grammar of polysynthetic languages differentially marks high vs. low Appl0 heads. Section 3. 2 analyzes low Recipient and Source applicatives along with low applicatives of stative possession. In section 3.3 low applicatives of unaccusative and inchoative verbs are discussed. Their morphological shape is accounted for based on a proposal of feature-delinking in the Morphological Structure (MS), (Harley & Noyer 1997). The delinking of the person features on the Appl0 head is argued to stem from the feature-geometry in the sense of Harley (1994) and universal feature hierarchy of Noyer (1992). The upshot of this morphological process is that instead of the morpheme inserted into the Appl0 head the morpheme realizing the Voice0 head shows up in the pre-base position of the verbal template. Section 3.4 discusses low applicatives formed from Noun- and Adjective-incorporated verbs and their distinct morphological shape is accounted for referring to the feature content on the Voice0 head and feature delinking on the Appl0 head. In section 3.5 a new type of low applicative construction is analyzed as a reflexive structure. The novelty in this analysis of these constructions is that the relation between the external argument and the theme, which is very similar to the applicative, is expressed through the reflexive 53 See the differenced between high and low applicative structures and their semantics in the Introduction, Section 1.4. 143 Voice head, which indicates the projection of an empty argument (PRO) in the specifier of the ApplP. This empty argument c-commanded and bounded by the external argument keeps the local low applicative relation with the theme. The structure thus contributes to the Recipient relation between the external argument and the theme. Section 3.6 analyzes the possessor dative constructions as low applicatives and it is argued that Georgian and related languages provide the semantic interpretations of stative possession in low applicatives through the little vBE head. The eventualities such as know, approve, etc., which have activity frame in these languages with nominative/ergative subjects, are capable of forming such relations. However, it is argued that psychological verbs denoting states in these languages only form high applicatives. This is due to the lower structural position of the dative experiencer argument itself, which prevents the projection of another dative applied argument in the structure. Section 3.7 introduces four-place complex predicates with location-as-object meanings that lexicalize a path component in their semantics. These complex applicative structures are argued to combine both high and low applicative heads since they show transfer-of-possession through the Recipient argument and also, the high applicative relation between a Benefactee argument and an event. Some of these complex predicates are argued to combine the causative head with the postpositional locative phrase in which animacy of the Goal argument is the key component. The following table summarizes low applicative structures analyzed in this dissertation and the types of little vs associated with their meanings: 144 Table 7. Low applicatives in Georgian TO Meaning/ type of v0 Transitive (vDO ) Unaccsusative/ Inchoative (vGO) Unergative (vDO) Psychological predicates of activities (vDO) Reflexive applicative (vDO) Dynamic Relation FROM Recipient Write, send, bake Arrive Source Lose, hide Static relation AT Stative Possessor Ripe, blossom Like, approve, adopt, etc. Bake, build Section 3.8 analyzes high applicatives formed from various classes of verbs such as psychological, unaccusative, and existential predicates. The three morphosyntactic classes of psychological verbs in Georgian discussed in Chapter 2 on causatives can differentially express low and high applicative meaning. For example, activity psych verbs can only express the low applicative relation, and the nom/erg/dative experiencers projected in these active structures are interpreted as voluntary, instigating subjects behaving like external arguments of transitive verbs. These active psychological verbs add a dative applied argument, which is interpreted as the possessor of the theme argument. The dative subjects of dynamic passive and stative psych verbs form high applicative relations as their dative arguments indirectly benefit from an event expressed by stative predicates. 145 Existential predicates such as ‘happen’, ‘occur’, etc. combine with the high applicative head in Spanish (Cuervo 2003). In Section 3.8 high applicatives formed from similar verbs are analyzed and also it is shown that they are morphologically realized the same way as low applicatives. Unaccusative and unergative verbs like ‘arrive’, ‘run’, and stative ‘hold’ may also form high applicatives in Georgian. A special Section 3.9 is dedicated to applicative constructions in related languages: Mingrelian and Svan, which show almost the same range of applicative meanings as Georgian. The following table summarizes the high applicative constructions and their correlation with the event-introducing v heads: Table 8. High applicatives in Georgian Psychological verbs of state (vBE) Unaccusatives of happening (vGO) Unergatives (vDO) Stative relation Like, love, hate Dynamic relation Happen, appear, occur Walk, dance Now I will review the proposals that are taken as the theoretical background for the analysis of applicative structures in this dissertation. 3.1.1 McGinnis on applicative structures as phases McGinnis’ (2004) proposal centers on the different syntactic properties of applicative heads (high and low) that may affect not only the phrase structure but also the phasal architecture of applicative constructions (Chomsky 1999, 2001). In her theory, low and 146 high applicative heads may differ in terms of their ability to demarcate the domain of the phase as predicted by (1): (1) The sister of VP heads a phase if an argument is generated in its specifier. Based on this condition McGinnis derives the differing properties of high and low applicatives in terms of their ability to form phases. Namely, the high applicative heads a phase since it is a sister of VP and, in combination with VP, it assigns a theta-role to the applied argument as seen in (2a). In contrast to the high applicative head, the low applicative head is not a phase head because it is not a sister of VP. In low applicatives, V0 may head a phase only in ‘special’ circumstances, i.e. when an argument is generated in its specifier. The following structures adapted from McGinnis illustrate this ability of Appl0 heads to head a phase: (2)a. High applicative = a phase vP DP v’ v ApplHP IO ApplH’ ApplH VP V DO 147 b. Low applicative phase vP DP v’ v VP V0 ApplLP IO ApplL’ ApplL DO In McGinnis’ system, DO stands for Direct Object i.e. the theme argument and IO for Indirect Object, i.e. the dative applied argument. As seen from these derivations, in the low applicative construction, the Appl0 head does not demarcate the phase boundary in the sense of Chomsky (2001), since the Appl0 is not a sister of VP. In contrast to low applicatives, the high applicative head is a phase head because the Appl0 head is a sister of VP and the IO, i.e. the applied argument, is projected in the specifier of ApplHIGH. In light ofMcGinnis’ findings, the question arising with respect to applicatives is whether the Appl0 heads in high and low structures are cyclic or not. The answer may be given either by syntactic tests or by morphological evidence such as the presence of Root-determined allomorphy of these heads. I follow Embick’s proposal (2009), discussed in the introduction, that this kind of allomorphy can be a test determining the cyclicity, in this case, of the Appl0 head. Specifically, if Root-conditioned allomorphy is present both in high and low applicative heads, then these heads cannot be cyclic. If the 148 opposite evidence is found, i.e. the heads do not show allomorphy, the prediction will be that these heads may be cyclic. One caveat for the syntactic structure of applicatives should be kept in mind though. In the low applicative, the Appl0 is introduced earlier in the derivation than the lexical V0 head itself. Due to this position of the Appl0 head, the expectation is that contextual allomorphy of the Appl-low0 will be impossible, because at the spell-out, the lower head cannot look ahead and ‘adjust’ to higher heads. Thus, the question about the cyclicity of the low Appl0 head may not be the right one to ask with respect to low applicatives. Another possible argument suggesting that the low applicative cannot be a cyclic head has to do with the amount of structure projected at the point of the derivation when this head is introduced. The low applicative relates two arguments: the theme and the dative applied argument projected under ApplP, but there is just one DP (theme) to be sent off to LF. Presumably, the structure of this size cannot satisfy the requirements of phase size, which has been argued by Chomsky (1999) to be of the size of the transitive vP. The situation is slightly different with high applicative heads. Based on McGinnis’ hypothesis, in contrast to the low applicative, the high applicative head defines the phase boundary. This means that when the high Appl0 head merges the lower structure will be sent off for LF/PF processing, and Root-determined allomorphy of this head will not be an option. This conclusion about the high applicative head will be examined in section 3.8 on high applicatives in this chapter. It should also be kept in mind that the categorydefining head (v), which has been argued by some morphologists to be a cyclic head 149 (Embick & Marantz 2008), may intervene between the Root and the high Appl0 head, which would render the Root-determined allomorphy of the latter head impossible. This is also expected in noun and adjective-incorporated unergative verbs where the categorydefining heads (n, a, etc.) may be overt and the morphemes realizing these heads would possibly intervene between the Appl0 head and the Root rendering the applicative morphemes resistant to root-conditioned allomorphy. Thus, the question whether the Appl0 head is cyclic or not may not be answered based on the absence of the contextual allomorphy of these heads. Another related question regarding the syntactic structure of applicative predicates is whether low or high applicative structures can be formed from verbs with various lexical semantic properties. The relevant observations in the existing literature will be shown next. 3.1.2 Transitivity restrictions on high and low applicatives (Pylkkanen 2002) Pylkkanen identifies several syntactic tests to distinguish between high and low applicatives. One such test for low applicatives is that they cannot occur with completely stative verbs such as ‘hold’. Here is the structure illustrating her point: (3) High applicative of stative * I held him a bag. (Pylkkanen 2002:24) Since English is a language which selects only the low applicative head to express the Recipient or the Source relations between the applied argument and the theme, the verbs whose lexical semantics are interpreted as stative eventuality such as in (3) cannot form Double Object Constructions (DOCs) with the mentioned thematic relations and 150 meanings. However, in Luganda, which is a high applicative language 54, stative events can combine with the high Appl0 head: (4) High applicative of stative verb Katonga ya- kwant- idde Mukasa K Past-hold- APPL- PAST M ‘Katonga held the bag for Mukasa.’ (Pylkkanen 2002: 25) ensawo. bag Pylkkanen’s main argument to distinguish high from low applicative is the existence of transfer-of-possession semantics between the applied argument and the theme. As seen in above structures in (3)-(4), in no way does the bag become the possession of the applied argument as the result of the event, although the high applied argument Mukasa benefits from the event described by the verb. Another syntactic restriction that Pylkkanen identifies is that only high applicatives can combine with unergatives, while low applicatives cannot. The following structures illustrate that applicative arguments are impossible in English; this is because English only has low applicatives, which require an internal applied argument to combine with the theme. Since unergatives lack internal applied arguments, low applicatives may not occur with them, and high applicatives are unavailable in English: (5) Applicative of unergative impossible in English: a. *I ran him. (unergative) (Pylkkanen, 2002: 24) [Intended meaning]: “I ran for him.” b.*I walked him. 54 It should be noted though that Pylkkanen’s (2002) analysis of applicatives does not exclude the possibility that there are languages which combine both high and low applicative heads and both types of structures may exist in the same language (cf. Cuervo (2003). 151 [Intended meaning]: “I walked for him.” The verbs in (5) cannot occur in DOCs in English to render the Benefactee reading for the applied argument. This means that in no way can the applied argument can either be a Recipient, or the Source. However, in the following Venda sentence, Pylkkanen demonstrates that high applicative is possible with the unergative verb: (6) Venda high applicative of Unergative verb Ndi-do-shum-el-s musadzi 1SG-FUT-work-APPL-FV lady ‘I will work for the lady’. (Pylkkanen 2002:25) Based on this evidence, it can be argued that some languages can form high applicatives with unergative verbs. Having established the contrast between high and low applicatives in terms of the verb classes that these heads can combine with, Pylkkanen also shows that thematic/semantic relations in an applicative sentence can also be used as a diagnostic: (7) Chaga high applicative n-a-y-lyi-`a m-k`a k-elya. Foc-1sg-PRES-eat-APL-FV 1-wife 7-food ‘He is eating food for his wife.’ (Bresnan & Moshi 1993: 49-50) In this Chaga example, food in no sense becomes a possession of wife, which can be used as another diagnostic for the high applicative, in contrast to low applicatives which entail a possession relation between the Theme and the applied argument. Thus, Pylkkanen concludes that only high applicative heads can combine with unergative verbs (as well as other verb classes) while low applicative heads must combine with various transitive structures. The restriction on stative eventualities combining with low 152 applicative heads has been modified by Cuervo (2003) given empirical evidence from Spanish which is discussed next. 3.1.3 Cuervo (2003) on low and high applicatives in Spanish Cuervo (2003) identifies several types of high and low applicative constructions in Spanish that allows the possibility of combining high and low applicative heads in the same language. Low applicatives in this language are DOCs in which three different types of relations can be established: recipient, source and stative possessor of the theme. She additionally illustrates that the low applicative head can combine with stative eventualities introduced by vBE, i.e. a stative event head, which, beyond the stative meaning of an event itself, can show the affectedness of the subject argument as well. Thus, the low applicative relation need not always express transfer-of-possession between the two arguments but may also imply just ‘a static relation of possession between two individuals’, as illustrated in the following examples: (8) Spanish low possessor applicatives a. Pablo le admira la paciencia a Valeria Pablo CL.DAT admires the patience.ACC Valeria.Dat ‘Pablo admires Valeria’s patience.’ (lit: Pablo admires Valeria the patience). b. Pablo le beso la frente a Valeria. Pablo CL.DAT. kissed the forehead.ACC Valeria.Dat ‘Pablo kissed Valeria on the forehead.’ (lit: Pablo kissed Valeria the forehead). 153 c. vP v Root Admiradmires ApplP DP A Valeria Appl0 DP la paciencia ‘patience’ (Adapted from Cuervo 2003:56) (8a) involves the state psychological verb admira ‘admires’ along with the stative possessor relation between the applied argument and the theme. However, (8b) is clearly an active structure where the same stative relation is expressed between the applied dative argument and the theme (Valeria and the forehead). This dissertation also shows empirical evidence from South Caucasian languages in which non-transfer predicates can be either stative (the Appl0 head combining with the stative verbs admire, have, see, envy, etc.), or dynamic (such as kiss, wash, touch, etc). What unites these stative and dynamic structures is their dative argument, interpreted as a stative possessor (or location) of the theme. Thus, these low applicatives have the meaning of ‘at’ (possessor) rather than ‘to’ (Recipient), or ‘from’ (Source) applicatives. The meaning of ‘at’ possessor applicatives is shown in the following formalism: (9) Low –APPL-AT (Possessor Applicative) x . y . f e s,t e. f (e, x) & theme (e,x) & in-the-possession (x, y) (Cuervo 2003:54) The formalism illustrates that there are two variables in low applicatives: the applied argument (y) and the theme (x), and the truth conditions of the low possessor applicative depend on the calculus of these variables. The denotation of this expression shows that 154 possessor datives are instances of DOCs and the relation between the theme and the applied argument includes the fact that the theme (x) must be in possession of an applied argument (y). The third type of applicative relation substantially widens the empirical base of applicative constructions cross-linguistically and clearly teases apart three types of low applicative meanings: Recipient (to), Source (from), and Possessor (at). The conclusions drawn from the above research will be applied to the analysis of applicative constructions in Georgian and related languages. Now I introduce the common properties of dative arguments in three types of high applicatives based on Cuervo (2003), which will be discussed in detail below: (10)a. dative arguments are all licensed by the Appl0 head; b. in some high applicatives, the dative argument is the highest argument in the structure (such as psychological verbs), occupies the subject position, and exhibits all properties of subjects; c. in Spanish, Experiencer subjects, like other dative subjects, never trigger agreement with the verb. (Agreement is with the nominative object); d. dative DPs are external to the vP that the Appl0 head takes as its complement. Therefore, there is no predication relation between the dative argument and the stative predicate, which means that only the stative theme and the verb enter into a predication relation. The properties in (10a-c) are descriptive statements and (10d) needs to be developed in detail. The externality of dative experiencers from predication relations with 155 nominative objects results from the fact that most psychological verbs in Spanish can appear without an experiencer. These are the following verbs: gustar ‘like’, importer ‘matter’, molestar ‘bother’, etc. These verbs are similar to the Italian piacere class, which were analyzed in Belletti & Rizzi (1988, henceforth, BR) and were argued to have the following structure: (11) S VP V' V piace NP a Gianni NP questo A Gianni piace questo. To G pleases this. In BR’s theory, the Experiencer argument Gianni asymmetrically c-commands the theme (questo) but either one can occupy the preverbal subject position. The structure for the high applicative of a psychological verb in Spanish has been presented in the introduction of this dissertation in (16) and here we are repeating for convenience as (12): (12) a. High applicative of psychological predicate A Daniela le Daniela.Dat CL.Dat ‘Daniela likes the cats.’ gustan los like.PL the gatos. cats. 156 b. ApplP Appl’ DPDAT a Daniela Appl le vP DPNOM los gatos v’ vBE Root gust- (Cuervo 2003: 135) It is evident that the nominative case is checked on the theme (los gatos) in a different position than the accusative in low applicative constructions with the possessor datives. The nominative argument is the subject of the vP ‘gustar’ (likes) rather than its object, as Cuervo argues. The dative experiencer is ‘external’ to the predication relation because the stative vP is the ‘first argument’ of the high App0 head that licenses the dative DP a Daniela. Thus, the predication relation holds between the verb and the nominative DP ‘cats’, while dative argument is ‘external’ to this relation. This is one of the characteristics of high applicatives according to Cuervo. It should be noted, though, that the above structure is not ‘right’ in a sense that it allows the dative DP a Daniela to be projected higher than the nominative theme object los gatos. This configuration could be objected to on the grounds that it would involve a minimality violation for the purposes of nominative case checking on the theme argument los gatos. This violation would not occur, if the nominative argument is projected higher than ApplP itself by some other functional head and the nominative case checked against Tns via Agree with this argument. However, we are assuming that the inherent dative case of the experiencer argument makes it invisible to the case-checking Agree relation, and hence the structure 157 does not incur a minimality violation for the nominative theme to check its case against Tns via Agree. These configurational properties of dative and nominative arguments in high applicatives substantially differ from those of experiencer and theme arguments in low possessor ‘AT’ applicatives. The contrast between low and high applicative meanings in psychological predicates is shown in the following sentences adapted from Cuervo (2003) again: (13) Low applicative A Laura le falta Laura.Dat CL. Dat lacks ‘Laura is missing Pablo’s pen.’ 55 la birome the pen de Pablo of Pablo (14) High applicative A Laura le gusta Laura.dat CL.Dat likes ‘Laura likes the / Pablo’s pen.’ la birome the pen (de Pablo) of Pablo In (14), the dative and nominative arguments are in different domains and do not relate to each other directly, as shown in the following tree: 55 In this sentence, the low applicative relation is established through the malefactive relation between the applied argument Laura and Pablo’s pen as shown in (27). 158 (15) ApplP DPDAT A Laura Appl’ Appl le vP DPNOM la birome de Pablo VBE Root gust- ‘like’ (Cuervo 2003:144) By contrast, in the existential construction (16), the relation between the theme and the predicate is not direct, but the dative argument Laura is in direct relation with the theme ‘pen’. Syntactically, this relation exists due to the low applicative head projecting the dative subject in the specifier and the complex theme as its complement: (16) Low applicative (=15) vP vBE v’ Root faltlack ApplP DPDAT A Laura Appl le DP la birome de Pablo ‘Pablo’s pen’ These two structures indicate the semantic and syntactic differences between high and low applicatives combining with stative vPs. Some of these arguments underlie the analyses of similar constructions in Georgian and related languages, in which the Appl0 heads are realized with several VIs, which is unlike Spanish where only the clitic le spells 159 out the Appl0 head. The interaction between the morpheme of the Appl0 head and other argument-structure changing morphemes will be explored in each subsection along with the syntactic and semantic relations between these arguments. 3.2 Low applicatives in Georgian 3.2.0 Introduction As mentioned in the literature review, three types of low applicative relations are found cross-linguistically: low recipient, source, and stative possession. An individual language may select all three, two, one, or none of them. This section illustrates that Georgian displays all three relations. 3.2.1 Low Recipient applicatives Pylkkanen (2002) and Cuervo (2003) define low applicatives as involving a dynamic transfer- of-possession, which can be literal (Maria gave John a book) or metaphorical (Maria showed Mercedes a book). There can be two types of transfer: either a transfer ‘to’ or a transfer ‘from’. The difference between the two meanings is essentially attributed to the two types of applicative heads, which define how the applied argument will be interpreted: as the Recipient or the Source of the theme object. Thus, in the following structures of Georgian the applied argument is interpreted as a Recipient: (17)a. nino-m ek’a-s c’ign-i N-Erg E-Dat book-Acc ‘Nino bought Ek’a the book. uq’ida. APPLIC- bought b. lali-m L-Erg gamo- ucxo. prev- APPLIC- baked 56 56 gia-s G-Dat namcxvar-i cake-Acc Recall that the abbreviations in this text stand for the following notions: ‘prev’ for preverbal marker of aspect and directionality; APPLIC- for the applicative marker; numbers stand for the person agreement affixes; Erg for ergative case, Dat for dative case and Acc for accusative case, etc. 160 ‘Lali baked Gia the cake.’ The dative applied arguments in these structures express the animate entities who ‘receive’ the object denoted by the theme. There is a clear sense that dynamic transfer-ofpossession occurs between an external and an applied arguments. In order for such a transfer to happen, the predicate must express a dynamic event of acquisition such as (buy), or creation (bake), etc. Levin & Rappaport Hovav (1991, henceforth, L& RH) argue that bake may denote either change-of-state or creation. With the former interpretation bake can participate in the inchoative/causative alternation (the cake bakes/ Sue baked the cake) while with the latter meaning the same verb participates in the benefactive alternation (bake a cake for someone/ bake someone a cake, L & RH 1991: 139). I claim that the verb in (17b) is one of creation, while that in (17a) is a change-ofstate. The products of these activities unambiguously belong to the class of dative applied arguments and the structures are therefore interpreted as low applicatives. The relation is applicative, if the arguments involved in applicative relations satisfy certain syntactic and morphological requirements. These requirements are: the applied argument must be assigned either inherent or structural dative case and projected in the specifier of the ApplP. In Georgian, the dative case of applied arguments in low applicatives must be structural because it changes into another case when the verb is in the Perfective series, specifically, into the postpositional genitive. How this dative and the accusative cases are checked on these arguments is discussed after presenting the derivation of low applicative structures in two series (Present and Perfective): 161 (18) a. lali-m gia-s L-Erg G-Dat ‘Lali baked Gia the cake.’ namcxvar-i cake-Abs gamo- ucxo. prev- APPLIC- baked 57 b. [VoiceP Lelam [voice’ [vP [VP [ApplP Gia-s [Appl’ namcxvari [Appl u-/i-]] cxo] v°] Voice°] c. The Present and the Aorist series low applicative VoiceP DPNOM/ERG Lela-m vP VP Voice’ Voice0 0 v [-features] - V0 cxo ‘bake’ Appl.arg. Appl’ Gia-s DPACC Appl0 [-features] [Dat] namcxvar-i u-/i‘ cake’ ApplP 57 Recall that the abbreviations in this text stand for the following notions: prev for preverbal marker of aspect and directionality; applic- for the applicative marker; numbers stand for the person agreement affixes; Erg for Ergative case, Dat for Dative case and Acc for Accusative case, etc. Also see the appendix 1 for fuller list of these glosses. 162 d. The Perfective series low applicative VoiceP vP VP ApplP DPDAT Lela-s Appl’ Voice0 v0 [-features, Case] - V0 cxo, ‘bake’ Appl’ . DPGEN.POST Gias-tvis DPACC namcxvari ‘cake’ Appl0 i-, u- As seen in (18c), the external argument is projected by Voice0 and in the aorist series, Voice0 checks the ergative case on this case-split external argument while in the Present series, Tns checks the nominative case feature on the same argument. The dative and accusative case features of two lower arguments in (18c) are checked as a bundle along with the phi-features of these arguments. As argued above, the dative case of the applied argument is structural and I assume that the accusative of the theme is also structural since the latter is specified on the DP in a certain syntactic configuration. Assuming bottom-up derivations for these constructions and the cyclicity of spellout of certain functional heads, specifically, that of little v0 (Chomsky 1999), I claim that the phi- and case feature of the Appl0 head is checked first against the applied dative argument via the head-specifier relation. I assume that when the little v0 head is merged, the dative applied argument is still ‘active’, so that it can still match its features against the probe of the v0 163 head which is looking down the structure for the goal and checks its case and phi-features again against the dative argument. Note that the applied dative argument must be marked, i.e. be specified for 1-2 persons in order to check the phi-features of the probe and get cross-referenced on the verb with the ‘m-set’ agreement markers 58. Recall from the Introduction that due to templatic constraints, only the most local marked argument to the v0 or Tns0 heads can be cross-referenced in the verbal template. Thus, I assume that the dative applied argument is privileged with respect to the person agreement marking than the lower Theme argument due to locality to the functional head specified for m-set agreement (v0 ). In this scenario, I am positing the possibility that one argument can check the phi-features of two functional heads (v0 and Appl0 ) as long as these heads are merged in the same phase, i.e. under the little v0. 59 The lower theme argument checks its accusative against the v0 via an Agree relation presumably. As illustrated by Chomsky 1995 and Bobaljik and Branigan 2006 among others, it is possible for one head to be specified for two different case features and particularly, the little v0 head across various languages has been posited to be specified for the dative and accusative case features. Due to locality, I suggest that the structurally marked dative argument does not incur a minimality violation as it is already deactivated by checking the phi- probe of v0 and this argument does not intervene between the theme 58 Thie discussion on how the cross-referencing of the arguments on verb happens is in the Introduction, Section 1.8. The definitions for two types of agreement and two sets of the person agreement markers ‘vset’ and ‘the m-set’ is also in the same section. 59 This type of checking pattern is again supported by the morphological evidence, i.e. the separate morphemes inserted into the Appl0 head and the person agreement presumably inserted in the little v0 head as argued by Lomashvili & Harley (in press). 164 and the v0 head for the latter to check its case features. Thus, the checking of case features in low applicatives may be accounted for with this kind of scenario. Further, we will be assuming that the similar checking pattern exists for other applied arguments and themes merged in DOCs. Note that in the Perfective series, however, this mechanism is a little different because the external argument is marked with the dative case and it absorbs the case feature of an applied argument projected in the specifier of the ApplP. This dative case of the subject is checked against the Appl0 head. Since the position of an applied argument is taken by the dative subject, the former dative applied argument is projected as an adjunct marked with the postpositional genitive. It can be argued that this structure is no longer the true Double Object Construction (DOC) because the genitive applied argument is no longer an argument of the Appl0 head. The position of the accusative argument stays the same and presumably, its case is checked against the same functional head as in (18c), i.e. v0 head. Since the merging site of the Appl0 head is below the event-introducing functional head (v), we assume that the dynamic transfer-of-possession is due to the Appl0 head in this construction. The phonological exponents of the low Appl0 head in Georgian are iand u-, which are sensitive to the features of the syntactic environment, i.e. the person features of the applied argument: (19) VIs for the applicative head in low applicative: 165 a. i- Applic0 low / [Dat] [+1] [+2] 60 b. u- Applic0 low / [Dat] [+3] d. - Applic0 low/ Elsewhere As we have seen in the above examples, the Vocabulary Items (VIs) realizing the Appl0 head in these low applicatives are i- and u-, which are sensitive to the phi-features of the dative applied argument. There is also - applicative marker in (19), which I assume is inserted into the Appl0 head in elsewhere contexts. Observe the following examples in which the elsewhere phonological exponent - is inserted into the Apll0 head and in some of these DOCs, a- shows up in the place of the applicative marker arguably inserted in the CAUSE: (20) Low Recipient applicatives: a. deda-m bavshveb-s velosiped-i Mother-Erg kids-Dat bicycle-Acc ‘Mother presented the kids a bicycle.’ b. mama-m dato-s surat-i Father-Erg D-Dat picture-Acc ‘Father showed Dato the picture.’ c. deda-m nino-s sachukar-i mother-Erg N-Dat present-Acc ‘Mother gave Nino a present.’ 60 achuka. CAUS- presented 61 aCAUS- chvena. showed mi- s- c- a prev- 3O- give- 3S The number symbols stand for the person agreement, i.e. 1-2 person arguments check the relevant features on the Appl0 head and i- is inserted while u- is inserted when the 3rd person DP checks the relevant feature. We do not use Halle’s (1997) features [ PSE] (Participant of the Speech Event) or Noyer’s (1992) [ Addressee] for the features of these arguments for the reasons that become clear later when the impoverishment of these features is discussed in Sections 3.3. and 3.4. 61 The affix a- is tentatively glossed as the VI for CAUSE by assumption that the transitive structures projecting external arguments may be generally interpreted as causative eventualities. We also assume that this a- in Georgian and related languages is a multi-functional morpheme whose secondary exponence can be something like TRANS head (Jelinek 1988), which projects the theme argument in transitive structures. For the detailed analysis of secondary exponence see Noyer (1997). 166 A direct transfer-of-possession happens in (20a & c) while a metaphorical transfer in (20b). Both low applicative meanings result from the attachment configuration. Note that some of these verbs can in fact realize the allomorphy i-/u- in certain contexts. The verb show ‘achvena’ in (20b) illustrates this: (21) Low applicative of ‘show’ m- ichvena 1S- APPLIC- showed ‘He/she showed me X.’ b. v- uchvene 1S- APPLIC- showed ‘I showed him/her X.’ However, two other verbs a-chuka ‘present’ and mi-s-c-a ‘gave’ do not show this allomorphy in any context: (22) Applicative of present and give impossible: a. *mo- m- isca prev- 1O- APPLIC- gave ‘He/she gave me X.’ b.* m- ichuka 1O- APPLIC- presented ‘He/ she presented me X.’ It is evident that the causative structure in (20b) can undergo applicativization while two other verbs (20a & c), which are semantically interpreted as the verbs of giving, resist this alternation, i.e. in no frame are they capable of including the phonological exponents i-/u- in their templates. The DOC data in (20) shows that the phonological exponents a-, i-, u- and - markers may be realized in the same third position of a ditransitive verb template. These items are inserted into different functional heads such as Appl0 or CAUSE in specific environments bearing a different complex of contextual 167 features. The question is why some of these verbs ‘resist’ the insertion of i-/u- exponents and the Appl0 head in some of these structures is realized with the null phonological exponent. I argue that the verbs of giving are ‘pure’ ditransitives and by default, such structures should deterministically project the applied argument along with two other main arguments—an external and a theme. In other words, the roots of such pure ‘ditransitive’ verbs when projected require the functional apparatus, which projects all three arguments. These types of structures may be considered as unmarked cases with respect to the applicative relation. Here are the structures illustrating this point: (23)a. John gave Mary a book. (Requires all three arguments) DOC b. *John gave a book. TRANSITIVE (24)a. Mary baked John a cake. (Adds the applied argument) DOC b. Mary baked a cake. TRANSITIVE As indicated in (23), give is by default a ditransitive verb and when projected it requires all three arguments to be realized in the clause. Therefore, the transitive structure with this verb is not good (23b). This verb is different from bake which can occur in the monotransitive frame and can also add the applied argument to form DOC. Halle & Marantz (1993: 133-134) argue that in certain environments UG may provide a zero spell-out as a default phonological realization of a morpheme in an unmarked case. They consider English present tense forms without a suffix as the Elsewhere case, where Tns is 168 realized by a default null suffix. 62 The conclusion is that the null phonological exponents are provided by the UG for unmarked cases and the same explanation may be assumed for the presence of null exponents for the Appl0 head in the verbs of giving since these semantically are unmarked with respect to the applicative relation. Note that the allomorphs of the Appl0 head are not phonological or prosodic contextdependent in the sense that they are not conditioned by the phonological or prosodic properties of Roots. They differ in terms of their substantive morphosyntactic features, such as [Dat] and phi-features, but they are not sensitive to the kinds of root-specific contextual features which condition the allomorphy of CAUSE in Georgian (Chapter 2) and the tense suffixes of English. Recall that the allomorphy of CAUSE in the inchoative-causative alternations of melt/melt type was Root-conditioned, i.e. the syllabicity of Roots was of importance in the insertion of causative markers. In English, /t/ and /d/ are allomorphs of the Past Tense and they impose certain conditions on the verbal stem, namely, that the former requires a voiceless stem-final consonant, while the latter requires a stem ending on the voiced segment. Thus, the phonological exponents /t/ and /d/ are the instances of contextual allomorphy. Georgian applicative markers do not impose such phonological or prosodic constraints on verbal stems but they do show verb class-determined allomorphy as illustrated in the above discussion. This raises the question of whether the Appl0 head is cyclic or not. The way to determine the cyclicity of the applicative head in a given structure comes from the allomorphy of this head across various verb classes. This proposal hinges on 62 The null suffix can also be homophonous, irregular and marked VI in other contexts, as it is the exponent of [+past] tense in the verbs like drive and hit. 169 empirical evidence shown in (20) where Roots are concatenated with the applicative morpheme in the template of a Georgian verb and no other morpheme intervenes between them. I repeat these examples here for convenience: (25) The position of the applicative morpheme with respect to Roots a. gamo- ucxo prev- APPLIC- bake ‘X baked someone a cake’ b. uchvena APPLIC- showed ‘X showed someone Y.’ I argue that the following assumptions are of relevance to determining whether the Appl0 head is cyclic or not: (26) The assumptions regarding the Appl0 head allomorphy: a. The allomorphs inserted in the Appl0 head may show the contextual allomorphy sensitive to the phonological properties of Roots; b. VI for the Appl0 head may be determined by the class of Root (the morpheme should impose certain constraints on the class of Roots, such as unaccusative, unergative, etc.). 63 As seen in above examples, the VIs inserted into the Appl0 head showed sensitivity to the person features of the dative applied argument and the null elsewhere item was inserted into this head with the verbs of giving. This evidence shows that the low Appl0 head may not be cyclic since it shows verb-class determined allomorphic selection, consistent with Embick’s proposal that contextual allomorphy can be conditioned by the 63 I assume that Roots are selected from the lexicon without categorical information (Marantz 1997, 2000) and that their syntactic behavior can be largely predicted based on the category-defining heads that they merge with. 170 class membership of Roots. The data from low Recipient applicatives demonstrate that the VIs realizing the Appl0 head show such sensitivity to the aforementioned Root properties. 3.2.2 Low Source applicatives An applied dative argument can be licensed by the Appl0 head in the environment of transfer predicates that express reverse directionality (Cuervo 2003: 51). This direction may come from the applicative relation of Source when the Source is projected by the Appl0 head in the specifier of the ApplP. The transfer-of-possession happens from the Source to an external argument. Typically, the source is marked with the dative case and the theme with the accusative case in such structures cross-linguistically. In Georgian, the same cases are assigned to the applied argument and the theme. The source is interpreted as a ‘possessor’ of the theme respectively: (27) Low source applicative a. erekle-m gia-s gasaɣeb-i E-Erg G-Dat key-Acc ‘Erekle hid the keys from Gia.’ da- umala. prev- APPLIC- hid b. dato-m lia-s c’ign-i dauk’arga. D-Erg L-Dat book-Acc prev- APPLIC- lost ‘Dato lost Lia’s book.’ (lit: Dato lost a book from Lia’s possession). c. nino-m mak’a-s k’aba gauq’ida. N-Erg M-Dat dress prev- APPLIC- sold ‘Nino sold Mak’a’s dress.’ (lit: Nino sold a dress from Mak’a’s possession). Notice that in all three examples, no direct transfer-of-possession occurs between the dative and external arguments. However, the relation between the dative applied 171 argument and the theme is one of possession. This relation is affected by the event whose endpoint marks the change of possession of the theme argument. Note that English NPs which correspond to the dative arguments in Georgian are assigned the genitive case in the translation, as they appear internal to the theme NP as possessors of the NP. This could be due to language-specific constraints on the selection of the Appl0 head by the verbal head in these structures. In Georgian, the assignment of genitive case to the Source correlates with the disappearance of the applicative marker from the verb. Note that in (26), the dative argument is interpreted as ‘affected’ since it loses the possession of the theme in all three structures. The same ‘affected’ meaning is not available for genitive possessors as shown in the following examples: (28) Genitive possessors a. erek’le-m gia-s gasaɣeb-i E- Erg G-Gen keys-Acc ‘Erek’le hid Gia’s keys.’ b. dato-m lia-s c’ign-i D-Erg L-Gen book-Acc ‘Dato lost Lia’s book.’ c. nino-m ketevan-is k’aba N-Erg K-Gen dress ‘Nino sold Ketevan’s dress.’ da- mala. prev- hid da- k’arga. prev- lost ga- q’ida. prev- sold The disappearance of the applicative morpheme in (28) indicates that the Appl0 head is not introduced in these structures and the applicative construction turns into the simple transitive. The possessor relation between the genitive cased-marked DP and the theme is kept. There is no relation between the possessor and the event. 172 Note that the morphological realization of low Source applicatives is i-/ u- as in low Recipient structures. The morpheme realizing the Appl0 head is sensitive to case and the phi- features of the dative argument ([Dat], [+1], [+2] and [+3]). These features on the DP presumably check the relevant uninterpretable person and case features on the functional head (Appl0). By assumption the case checking pattern of the lower dative and the accusative theme arguments is the same here as in the low recipient applicatives shown above. We do not repeat it here. By contrast to low Recipient applicatives, there is no evidence of Root-determined contextual allomorphy of the Appl0 head in these low Source constructions. I tentatively assume that low Appl0 head in these constructions is not a cyclic head. 3.2.3. Low state applicatives: Possessor Datives (AT) Recall that Spanish has low applicative structures formed by state and dynamic action verbs which do not express transfer-of-possession either literally or metaphorically. The following structures illustrate Cuervo’s point repeated here as (29): (29) State and dynamic applicatives (at) a. Pablo le admira la paciencia a Valeria Pablo CL.DAT admires the patience.ACC Valeria.Dat ‘Pablo admires Valeria’s patience.’ (lit: Pablo admires Valeria the patience). b. Pablo le beso la frente a Valeria. Pablo CL.DAT. kissed the forehead.ACC Valeria.Dat ‘Pablo kissed Valeria on the forehead.’ (lit: Pablo kissed Valeria the forehead). (Cuervo 2003: 53) There is no sense in which the dative argument ‘gets’ or ‘loses’ the theme in these structures: simply, the applied argument is understood as the possessor (or the Location) of the theme. 173 In Georgian, similar structures have slightly different meanings as showed in the following: (30) Dative possessors (AT) a. dato-m lia-s motmineba D-Erg L-Dat patience ‘Dato approved Lia’s patience.’ mo- uc’ona prev- APPLIC- approved (31) Datives of activities (AT) lela-m bavshv-s loq’eb-i da- uk’ocna. L-Erg kid-Dat check-Acc prev- APPLIC- kissed ‘Lela kissed a kid’s cheeks.’ (Lit: Lela kissed the kid on the cheeks) Dative arguments are interpreted as stative or inalienable possessors of the same possesseee. Patience and work are themes that are abstract entities cultivated by the applied dative arguments. The event semantics of psychological verbs in these structures can be interpreted as activities as opposed to states. As mentioned earlier in Section 2.8, in Georgian, the psychological verb ‘like’ as well as love, hate, etc. comes in three semantic and morphological shapes denoting state, dynamic passive, and active events. The fact of interest is that only activity verbs project external arguments and can add the dative applied argument via the Appl0 head. This ability of activity psych verbs to add dative applied arguments correlates with low applicative meaning. In Spanish, as noted by Cuervo, low applicative meaning (possessor AT) can be expressed by certain psychological verbs denoting states, which project just the dative experiencer and the theme. Indo-European languages, including Spanish, lack the morpho-semantic variety of psychological verbs found in Georgian and related languages. The interpretation of psychological verbs in these languages is mainly stative. In what follows I illustrate that 174 in Georgian, a low applicative possessor relation is expressed only in those structures where the dative applied argument is added to the argument structures of active psychological verbs. It should be kept in mind that the relation between the dative applied argument and the theme is still one of stative possession as illustrated in (30)-(31). The low applicative meaning expressed by the activity verb ‘kiss’ in (31) shows inalienable possession of the theme by the dative argument. This possessor-possessee relation introduces two variables in the structure: the theme and the possessor dative argument. Here is the structure demonstrating this relation: (32) Low possessor applicatives a. dato-m lia-s motmineba D-Erg L-Dat patience ‘Dato approved Lia’s patience.’ mo- uc’ona prev- APPLIC- approved b. [vP Neli [v’ [VP [ApplP Kato [Appl’ shroma [Appl° u-]] pasa] [v° Ø]] c. vP DPNOM/ERG ext.arg Dato-m VP ApplP DPDAT Appl.arg Lia-s v’ v0 V0 c’on- ‘approve’ Appl’ DP Appl0 Theme u‘motmineba’ ‘patience’ The morphological realization of the Appl0 head in this low possessor applicative is the same as in other types of low applicatives: the Recipient and the Source as illustrated above. The VIs inserted into the Appl0 head show the same kind of free allomorphy 175 which is sensitive to substantive features of the dative argument. Since the group of predicates showing such possessor relations is not large, it is hard to test whether the VI - is also available as an elsewhere item or not. It can be argued that based on these structures, there is no enough evidence to determine whether the Appl0 head is cyclic or not. The vocabulary items are inserted in the contexts which are determined by the substantive morpho-syntactic features of dative arguments. This kind of sensitivity may be taken as evidence for non-cyclic Appl0 head. For the purposes of comparison of these structures with the genitive possessor constructions, the following structures may shed light on the change in meaning and the morphological spellout of verbs: (33) Genitive stative possessors a. neli-m rusudan-is motmineba N-Erg R-Gen patience ‘Neli approved Rusudan’s patience.’ b. deda-m bavshv-is loq’eb-i Mother-Erg kid-Gen cheeks-Acc ‘Mother kissed the kid’s cheeks.’ mo- ic’ona. prev- REFL- approved da- k’ocna. prev- kiss Along with the change in meaning, which is entailed as the result of the subtraction of one variable (dative applied argument) from the corresponding applicative structure, the verbal morphology also undergoes changes. The VI i- preceding the Root c’on- in (33a) can be analyzed as a Reflexive marker for a number of reasons. This VI is not sensitive to the phi-features of the applied argument and the series features of T0 or Infl0 like other morphemes that realize event heads in the same position. The details of the insertion are not relevant here, although they will be analyzed below, in Section 3.5 dealing with 176 reflexive applicatives. The following examples illustrate that the prefix i- is sensitive neither to the person feature of an external experiencer argument, nor to that of the theme: (34) The psychological predicate and its morphology a. mo- v- ic’one prev-1S- REFL - like ‘I liked it.’ b. mo- ic’one prev- REFL- liked ‘You liked it.’ c. mo- ic’ona prev- REFL- liked ‘He/she liked it.’ Ignoring other morphemes in this paradigm, it is evident that the affix i- is not sensitive to the person feature of any argument projected in the clause (See Appendix A for detailed explanation of the homophony of this VI with other morphemes). The subject is assigned nom/erg/dative cases like the external arguments of DOCs or transitive verbs and the theme is assigned accusative. The checking pattern of these cases is the same as in Recipient applicatives shown above. For the interpretation of meaning in these structures only the theme argument is interpreted as a variable related to the event calculus of the applicative phrase. 3.3 Low applicatives of unaccusative and inchoative verbs 3.3.0 Introduction In Georgian unaccusative verbs, a low applicative relation can be expressed between the dative subject argument and the theme projected by the internally caused change-ofstate verbs. Cuervo (2003) also discusses similar applicative constructions in Spanish but 177 none of her examples shows the Recipient relation between the dative applied argument and the theme. Instead, in her analysis, the notion of affectedness better accounts for the dative argument in the following applicatives whose event structure is argued to be complex, as in other inchoative verbs: (35) Affected applicatives formed from inchoatives a. A Carolina se le rompio el florero. Carolina.Dat CL.Ref CL.Dat broke the vase ‘The vase broke on Carolina.’ (Lit: ‘To Carolina broke the vase.’ ) b. [TP T [vP2 [vGO se] [ApplP [A Carolina] [Appl’ [Appl le] [vP1 vBE + root [el florero]]]]]] c. TP Tense VGO se- vP2 ApplP DPDat A Carolina Appl’ Appl0 le vP1 DPobj vbe + Root (Cuervo 2003: 112) The structure of the affected applicative in (35) represents a complex event which can be decomposed into the higher vGO, usually introducing change-of-state semantics in inchoatives (fall, grow, break, etc.), and the lower vBE head, which expresses the resultant state. The dative applied argument is sandwiched between these vPs, staying external to vPGO. No external argument is licensed in these structures. In this sense, affected applicatives are distinct from low applicatives and they are analyzed as a distinct kind of relation. None of the low applicative relations (Recipient, Source, and the Possessor) is present in the affected applicative illustrated above. 178 3.3.1 Empirical data and syntactic analysis In what follows I argue that in applicatives of internally or externally-caused changeof-state verbs, as well as in certain inchoative and transitive verbs a low applicative relation obtains between the dative subject and the theme with the same morphological realization of all these diverse structures: (36) Applicatives of unaccusative, inchoative and transitive verbs a. m- epurčkn- eb- a 64 1S- voice- blossom- TH- 3O ‘It is blossomed for me. ( Lit: ‘I am blossomed it.’) b. m- ezrd- eb- a 1S- voice- grow- TH- 3O ‘It is grown for me.’ (Lit: ‘I am grown it.’) c. m- eɣeba 1S- voice- open- TH- 3O ‘It is opened for me.’ (Lit: ‘I am opened it.’) d. m- ec’ereba 1S- voice- write- TH- 3O ‘It is written for me.’ (Lit: ‘I am written X.’) e. m- exvneb- a 1S- voice- plow- TH- 3O ‘It is plowed for me.’ (Lit: ‘I am plowed it.’) f. m- eteseb- a 1S- voice- sowed- TH- 3O ‘It is sowed for me.’ (‘I am sowed it.’) The dative subject argument in these structures is interpreted as the Benefactee of an event expressed by the verb. The theme argument undergoes internally or externallycaused change-of-state and, literally or metaphorically, the nominative theme argument 64 In these structures, the Dative subject is indexed with the m-set markers in verbs based on the locality with the v0 head (see section 1.6 of Introduction for more details). 179 ends up in the possession of this higher dative argument. This meaning should involve the low applicative head that relates the dative argument to the theme. Also, notice that the morphological shape of these applicatives is uniform, although the event semantics of these verbs is not the same. In (36a & b), the events are internally-caused changes-ofstate, while in (36c & f), the themes undergo externally caused changes-of-state. Generally, the verbs in (36d-f) are transitive, as opposed to inchoatives and unaccusatives in (36a-c). It may be suggested that the structures with the transitive verbs are passivized versions of the corresponding DOCs in which the applied argument becomes the subject of passive. The applicative in (36a) cannot appear in the transitive frame under any argument-structure changing operation. Irrespective of these differences, the derivation of all these events should involve the Appl0 head that relates the dative Benefactee argument to the theme and this relation can be expressed locally by these arguments. Before sketching the derivations for these structures, note that the event structure of the applicatives involves both simple and complex events and some of these structures should be analyzed individually. Following Cuervo (2003), I suggest that the internallychanged verb ‘blossom’ gaipurchkna consists of a simple event with the vPGO expressing a change: (37) The structure of a simple event of change (gaipurchkna) ga- ipurchkna prev-REFL- blossom ‘It blossomed.’ vPGO VP DP v0 Root purchkna ‘blossom’ 180 The structures in (36d, e & f) clearly represent the passives of ditransitive verbs such as John sowed Alex the field in which Alex becomes the subject of the passive sentence shown in (36f). Below it will be argued that this is supported with the non-active voice morphology in these forms (the affix e-). The structure of a simple transitive verb corresponding to the mentioned passive would be the following: (38) The structure of an event in simple transitives: Da- tesa Prev- sowed ‘He sowed X.’ vPDO VP v0 DP Root ‘sow’ tes However, the Roots like grow, open etc. that form the core of the applicatives in (36b & c) can participate in the inchoative/causative alternation and in their inchoative frame, they represent complex events combining two vPs in the derivation. It may be argued that the underlying structure of inchoatives can be the same as in other languages. Here is a structure of inchoative events adapted from Cuervo (2003): (39) The structure of the inchoative = (36b&c) vPGO vPBE vGO DPNOM v’ VBE VP Root … (Adapted from Cuervo 2003:104) 181 Observe that vGO in these structures does not project an argument. Only the lower stative head of vPBE does. The subject of inchoative verbs is assigned the morphological nominative case across all three series. This case suggests that the subject in the construction like (36b & c) is like the underlying object of the corresponding transitive/causative structure, although it displays almost all of the properties of transitive verb subjects. As seen from (37)-(39), the verbs in (36) have different underlying syntax, namely the event-introducing heads (little vs) are different in them and in (39) the event structure is complex as it combines two vs (vPBE and vPDO). I propose that the applicatives of various event types, shown in (38)-(39), have one common structural property: they introduce the ApplP whose head projects the dative applied argument in the specifier of this projection. Since a Recipient relation exists between the dative applied argument and the theme, structurally these arguments must be in the same local domain and ideally would be related to each other by the Appl0 head when the dative argument is projected as the specifier of the Appl0 head and the nominative argument as the sister of this head. However, the analysis of other Recipient low applicatives has shown that the theme argument was projected as the sister of the Appl0 head (bearing the accusative case in Spanish and Georgian). This creates a problem for the analysis of the nominative theme arguments in applicatives of inchoative, or internally-caused change-of-state verbs. The nominative case-marked theme must be projected as the subject of vP as shown in (39). Dative arguments in these structures are also different from dative arguments in DOCs. Recall from the introduction of the dissertation (Section 1.7, example (29)) that, 182 in the Perfective series, dative applied arguments are uniformly assigned the postpositional genitive and the applied argument is demoted to an adjunct position due to this change in case marking. Observe the difference of the case in the Perfective series verbs and the dative subjects of inchoative verbs: (40) a. Genitive applied arguments of DOC in the Perfective: Dato-s Gia-s-tvis saxl-i aushenebia D-Dat G-Gen.for house-Acc Prev- APPLIC- build ‘Dato (apparently) has built the house for Gia.’ b. Dative Benefactor argument of unaccusatives in the Perfective series: Dato-s q’vavil-i ga- purchknebia. Dato-Dat flower-Nom Prev- blossom ‘The flower has (apparently) blossomed for Dato.’ Thus, in DOCs, the Appl0 head checks the structural dative case of the applied argument as opposed to internally-changed and other activities shown in (36) and (40b) where the inherent dative case is marked on the Benefactee. Given these distinctions between the dative cases on applied arguments in (36) and the applied argument in DOCs, below I argue how structural and inherent cases on dative arguments are checked without incurring minimality violations. First let us analyze the properties of the theme arguments in applicatives of inchoatives. As mentioned above, these nominative themes are underlyingly like nominative subjects of unaccusative and inchoative verbs. However, these arguments must be c-commanded by the dative Benefactees as illustrated by the native speaker judgments. Therefore, the nominative theme which is a possessee of the dative argument must be projected lower in the tree. I propose that the dative benefactee and theme 183 arguments in applicatives of inchoatives and internally-caused change-of-state verbs are projected under the ApplP. I assume that case checking of the arguments may happen from other functional heads rather than from those which license these arguments (such as the Appl0 head may not check the nominative case of the theme, although the latter is selected as its complement): (41) a. m-e-teseba ‘It is sown for me’ b. m-e-ɣeba ‘It is opened for me.’ c.[VoiceP [TP [T’ [vPDO/GO [DPnom [vPBE [VP [ApplP DPdat Appl°] purchkn] vBE ] vDO/GO] T] e-]] d. VoiceP Voice0 TP T0 vPDO/GO vDO/GO vPBE ApplP DPDAT appl.arg. V0 purchkn, tes, ‘blossom, ‘sow’ Appl’ Appl0 DPNOM theme i-, uThe benefactee does not represent a barrier for the case checking relation between the nominative theme and the T0 due to its inherent dative case. Thus, the dative case on these higher Benefactee arguments is checked against the Appl0 head and the nominative case on the theme against T0 via Agree. 3.3.2 Analysis of morphological marking The morphological shape of the inchoative applicatives indicates that, instead of the i-/u- and - exponents of the Appl0 head, the voice marker e- shows up in the pre-base 184 position of the argument structure-changing morphemes. Recall from Chapter 2 that the same VI appears in contexts where the head of the VoiceP projection bears the [NonActive] feature. I assume that this feature is also present on the Voice head in these constructions, and consequently, Voice0 does not project the external argument in these constructions. The question arises as to why the morpheme realizing the Voice0 shows up instead of the VI of the Appl0 head. Recall from the introduction (Section 1.7) that in Georgian and related languages, language-specific constraints are imposed arbitrarily on the verbal template and they allow only one argument structure-affecting morpheme to be realized in the pre- and the post-base positions. The following schema shows this constraint: (42) … ___________ Root/Base __________ … Applicative, Voice, Causative, Causative Voice, Antipass, etc. These functional heads affecting the argument structure have just two positions-ofexponence in the verbal template, one in the pre-base and another in the post-base position. In inchoative applicatives, only one VI marking either the Applicative or the Voice head can receive a spell-out in the verbal template. The data in (36) shows that only the VI e- realizing the Voice0 is inserted. The question is what privileges the VI of Voice over the Applic0. There can be two different answers to this question. The first could be provided by a pre-insertion impoverishment rule, which changes the feature content on certain functional heads (Halle & Marantz 1993, Halle 1997) bleeding the insertion of the 185 applicative morpheme. The second answer could be provided by the existence of a null exponent for the Appl0 head in certain contexts. For the first scenario, I propose that an impoverishment rule applies to the person features of the Appl0 head. The impoverishment in this approach is represented as delinking, which means that the delinking of certain features entails the delinking of features dependent on them. I follow Noyer (1992) and Harley (1994) in positing this process and in recognizing that the following hierarchy of features: 12 3 pl dual fem underlies the feature geometry shown in (43). In Georgian, delinking of the feature [+1] entails delinking of [+2] and consequently, of [+3] while the case feature [Dat] dominates the phi-features and it is kept intact since the delinking applies just to person agreement features: (43) Impoverishment as Delinking [Dat] [Dat] [+1] [+ 2] [+ 3] As the result of this delinking, only the dative case feature will be left on the Appl0 head and the phonological exponent of Voice0 will be realized in the same position unobstructed. The second solution is compatible with the syntactic structure that these verbs project and the feature content on the heads that introduce arguments in these applicatives. As argued above, the Voice cannot project an external argument due to the feature [NonActive] and the dative Benefactee/Recipient has the same relation to the theme as other dative applied arguments in DOCs. It could be that the feature content on the Voice has some relevance for the phonological realization of the Appl0 head. A zero exponent 186 for Appl0 may be inserted in elsewhere contexts as argued in Section 3.2 on low applicatives. Recall that the verbs of giving appear to realize a null exponent of the Appl0 head. Similarly, I may argue that the null elsewhere item is inserted into the Appl0 head in structures where the Voice head bears this specific [NonActive] feature due to which it cannot project an external argument. The presence of this null exponent does not prevent the exponent of [NonActive] feature from being realized in the same position as the VI of the Appl0 head. As for the preference between these two analyses, it can be argued that the second is more ‘economical’ because it does not need to posit the special rule for featural economy as presented in the delinking analysis. Halle (1997), Siddiqi (2009) among many others argue for both featural and exponential economy whereby UG restricts the featural content on the nodes positing only those morphosyntactic features which are relevant for the derivation of the structure. Siddiqi (2009) argues for the principle that minimizes exponence, i.e. the derivation realizes “all the formal features of the derivation with the fewest morphemes” (Siddiqi 2009:4). These are two different kinds of economy principles that are active in vast majority of languages and I may also argue following these accounts that the ‘Rule economy’ could be a better option for explaining the appearance of the Voice morpheme in above applicatives. 3.4 Low applicatives of Noun/Adjective-incorporated predicates The following set of verbs illustrates low applicatives of noun- or adjectiveincorporated (henceforth, NI and AI) verbs which project dative Benefactee subjects and 187 nominative theme arguments undergoing a change-of-state. These structures resemble the applicatives in the above section in many ways: (44) Applicatives of AI- and NI- incorporated verbs a. m- imc’ip- deb- a 1S- APPLIC- ripe- pass- TH- 3O ‘It is ripened for me.’ (lit: ‘I am ripened.’) 65 b. m- iɤvin- deb- a 1S- APPLIC- wine- pass- TH- 3O ‘It is wined for me.’ (lit: ‘I am wined’) c. m- ilp’eb- a 1S- APPLIC- decompose- TH- 3O ‘It is decomposed on me.’ (lit: ‘I am decomposed it.’) d. misc’or- d- eb- a 1S- APPLIC- straight- pass- TH- 3O ‘I am satisfied with it.’ (lit: ‘I am straightened.’) 66 e. m- itvinier- deba 1S- APPLIC - tamepass- TH- 3O ‘It is tamed for me.’ (lit: ‘I am tamed X.’) f. m- isxr- eb- a 1S- APPLIC- heal- TH- 3O ‘It is healed on me.’ (lit: ‘I am healed it.’) Note the difference between the morphological shape of these applicatives and that shown for the inchoative applicatives in (44). In these structures, the pre-base position of the argument structure-changing morphemes is realized with i-/u- allomorphy, which is sensitive to the person feature of the dative subject. This can be seen in the following examples: (45) Adj-incorporated applicatives 65 66 I assume that all these forms in English are impossible. The latter verb has acquired idiomatic meaning recently—‘I like something.’ 188 a. m- imc’ip- d- eb- a 1S- APPLIC- ripepass- TH- 3O ‘I am ripened’ b. g- imc’ip- deb- a 2S- APPLIC-ripepass- TH- 3O ‘You are ripened.’ c. umc’ip- deb- a APPLIC- ripepass- TH- 3O ‘He/she is ripened.’ The Voice0 head in these structures is not active since no external argument is projected into the clause. The applicative relation is interpreted as low because the theme argument undergoing the change-of-state directly benefits or affects the subject argument. Another morpheme of interest in these structures is the post-base –d, which realizes either the Voice0 head or some verbalizer functional head v0. I analyze this morpheme as another VI of Voice0. The reason will become clear below in this section where the interaction between the VIs realizing the Voice and Appl0 heads is analyzed. This -d consistently shows up in Noun or Adjective-incorporated unergatives as well as the dynamic passive psychological predicates: (46) AI and NI dynamic events a. mc’ip- dripe- pass‘It is ripened.’ b. tvinier- dtamepass‘It is being tamed.’ eba TH- 3S eb- a TH- 3S Following Hale & Keyser’s theory of argument structure (2002) these forms may be analyzed as Noun and Adjective-incorporated verbs in which the Roots are incorporated 189 into the verbalizing v0 head. Following Harley (1995), I assume that the verbalizing head may be interpreted as BECOME. In Cuervo’s system, this v0 head may be interpreted as the vGO of changes. The derivation of the applicative construction from these verbs will involve a low Appl0 head projected below VP, and this VP is composed of the acategorical Root first combining with a categorizing head of an adjective or a noun (a, n) and then conflated with the empty V0 head, as shown in the following structure: (47) Noun/Adj- incorporated applicative m-i-mc’ip-d-eb-a Lit: ‘I am ripened.’ VoiceP Voice0 [NonActive] -d TP T0 VPBECOME v0 VP V0 ApplicP DPDAT Appl.arg. Appl’ DPNOM Adj/N Appl0 V0 m’c’ipe‘ripe’ a/n As seen from this structure, the dative argument is projected in the specifier of the ApplP and the argument checks its inherent dative case against Appl0 head. The nominative case of the lower theme argument is checked against Tns via Agree since there is no structurally-marked argument intervening between this nominative theme and the T0. Next we address why the VI of the Appl0 head shows up in the pre-base position rather than the Voice0 morpheme. Note that the Voice0 head specified for [NonActive] 190 feature was realized as e- in the applicatives of inchoatives, while in NI and AIapplicatives the Voice0 head is additionally specified for [+A] and [+N] features. It can be assumed that Roots enter the derivation with the same features and VI for these features is (-d). Thus, the following items can be inserted into the Voice0: (48) VIs for Voice0: a. -d Voice0 [NonActive]/ Roots [+ N], [+ A]____ b. e- Voice0 [NonActive]/ Roots (inchoative, etc.)_____ c. - Voice0 [NonActive] / Elsewhere The post-base position of the argument structure-changing morphemes will be filled by –d due to the Elsewhere principle which privileges the VI with more specific feature specifications compatible with the environment where it is inserted. Thus, I claim that when –d is discharged in the post-base position and the pre-base position remains empty for the VI realizing the Appl0 head, the VIs of this head will be inserted. This kind of relation between the VIs realizing the Voice can be called as discontinuous feeding (Noyer 1997) with which the two exponents of the same head do not bleed each other, rather the insertion of one exponent such as that of Voice in the post-base position ‘feeds’ the pre-base position by insertion of the phonological exponent of the Appl0 head. This happens with the VIs of the Voice0 and Appl0 head in above examples. Thus, DM provides adequate explanation of the morphological shape of NI and AI applicatives. 3.5 Reflexive applicatives 3.5.0 Introduction 191 Georgian and related languages can express a benefactive relation between an external argument and a theme with dynamic events. Verbs that participate in the paradigm are of wide semantic variety such as creation (bake, cook, prepare, etc.), locative/locatum (sew, stitch, load, etc.), etc. These are typical transitive structures projecting agentive external arguments where the latter are assigned the nom/erg/dat cases across series. The applicative relations of Recipient and Source are formed between the external argument and the theme and this distinguishes them from regular transitive structures. Essentially, the external argument acts like the dative applied argument in DOCs in many respects. However, the relation between the dative applied argument and the theme in DOCs is one of transfer-of-possession, while in these constructions, which I provisionally refer to as reflexive applicatives, the theme is in the prospective possession relation with the external argument. First, observe the examples: (49) Reflexive applicatives: a. lela sach’mels imzadebs L-Nom food REFLprepare ‘Lela is preparing the food for herself.’ b. gela-m shuki ainto G-Erg light prev- REFL- switch ‘Gela turn on the light for himself.’ c. aleksi-m xaliča gaishala. A-Erg. carpet-nom prev- REFL- spread ‘Alex spread the carpet for himself.’ d. me saxli av- ishene. I-Erg house prev- 1S- REFL- built ‘I built the house for myself.’ . e. nino-m N-Erg . namcxvari cake gamo- icxo. prev- REFL- bake 192 ‘Nino baked a cake for herself.’ f. shen kart’opili she- ic’vi You-Erg potatoes prev- REFL- fry ‘You fried potatoes for yourself.’ . Notice that all these forms have the VI i- in the pre-base position. In contrast to the applicative markers i-/u-, this morpheme is not sensitive to the person features of the external argument that can be seen from (49d, e & f), where the subjects are of three different persons: first, third, and second respectively. Below I argue that this i-realizes the reflexive voice head rather than the Appl0. Recall that the transfer-of-possession relation between the dative argument and the theme was the defining structural feature of low applicatives in Pylkkanen (2002) and the subsequent work. Therefore, it may be assumed that morphologically such a semantic relation will have to be expressed differently than applicatives with transfer-of-possession relation between the external and Theme arguments. External arguments and themes should not form close-knit semantic relationships. Nevertheless, this appears to be present here. First, note that in the following reflexive verbs, VI i- occupies the pre-base position of the argument structure-changing morphemes: (50) Reflexives in Georgian a. ek’am tav-i da- ibana. E-Erg. head-Acc prev- REFL-washed ‘Ek’a washed her head.’ b. dato-m p’ir-i ga- ip’arsa. D-Erg face-Acc prev- REFL- shaved. ‘Dato shaved his face.’ These verbs denote dynamic events directed towards one’s own body parts. The phonological exponenet i- shows the same properties as the one in the applicative 193 structures in (49). Specifically, this i- is not sensitive to the person features of the external argument or to the series features as is detected with the same exponent of the Voice0 with unergative verbs. Below I argue that this i- is the exponent of the reflexive Voice: (51) The VI i- in unergatives across series: a. Present series v- cek’v- av67 1S- dance- TH ‘I am dancing.’ b. Aorist series v- icek’v- e 1S- VOICE- dance- Aor ‘I danced.’ c. Perfective series m- icek’v- ia 1S-VOICE- dance- TH- 3O ‘I have (apparently) danced.’ Thus, I argue that the phi-feature insensitive i- realizes not the Appl0 head but rather the reflexive Voice in (49). Note also that the exponent i- is not found in many transitive structures as illustrated in the following: (52) Transitive activities a. v- ch’- am 1S- eat- TH ‘I eat X.’ b. v- c’er 1S- write ‘I write it.’ c. v- tamash- ob 1S- play- TH 67 Note that in (61a) the insertion of the reflexive morpheme is sensitive to the series features, i.e. in [present] the default VI - is inserted into the Refl0. 194 ‘I play X.’ This evidence will support the analysis of the morphosyntax of reflexive causatives which is discussed next. 3.5.1 Analysis of morphosyntax of reflexive applicatives I propose that both reflexive and reflexive applicative structures combine the same reflexive Voice realized with the exponent i- in their derivation with the eventintroducing and lexical heads (vDO and V0). In reflexive applicatives, the ApplP also merges. Presumably, the exponent of the reflexive Voice bleeds the affixes i-/u- of the Appl0. Summarizing what I have said above, the structure for the ‘pure’ reflexive events should be the following: (53) The structure for reflexives a. da- ibana prev-REFL- washed ‘He/she washed (his head).’ b. [VoiceP External Arg [vPDO [ReflP [VP theme bana] [Refl° i] ] vDO] Voice°] c. VoiceP DPNOM/ERG Voice’ vPDO VP DPACC Tavi ‘head’ VoiceREFL ivDO V0 bana ‘wa 195 This configuration of the Voice head with respect to the theme does not necessarily entail a close relation between the external argument and the theme but the import of this structure will soon become clear when the structure of reflexive applicatives is analyzed below. I conceptualize ‘pure’ reflexives much like high aplicative structures where the relation obtains between the external argument and an event. Inalienable possession does not need to be represented with the local relation between the arguments. Likewise, the benefactive and prospective possession meaning between the external argument ands the theme in reflexive applicatives can be attributed to the low attachment site of the Appl0 head, which relates the theme to the external argument through some syntactic mechanism. In syntax, this relation is implemented in the following way: The reflexive Voice head reflects that the Appl0 head has projected PRO in the specifier of the ApplP rather than the full dative applied argument. This empty element is coindexed with the external argument. The accusative theme can thus be selected by the Appl0 head: (54)a. Gela-m shuk-i a- into. Gela-Erg light-Acc prev- APPLIC- switch ‘Gela turned on the light for himself.’ 196 b. VoiceP DPNOM/ERG Gela-m Voice’ vPDO DPACC 68 VP ApplP PRODAT VoiceREFL ivDO’ vDO V0 nto ‘switch’ Appl’ Appl0 i-/uThe accusative case of the theme can be checked against vDO via Agree since no DPACC other argument intervenes between the theme and this functional head to incur the minimality violation. I assume that the case of the external argument is checked against the Voice0 and Tns depending on the series features (Present or Aorist). Thus, applicative relations can be expressed via the empty argument PRO and the reflexive Voice head in these structures. The transfer-of-possession meaning between the external argument and the theme can be obtained through the local relation between these arguments. Language-specific templatic restrictions are responsible for bleeding the exponent of the Appl0 head and leaving the reflexive Voice exponent in the surface structure. A somewhat similar proposal about the ReciprocalP has been advanced in Ndaiyragije (2006) about Kirundi, a Bantu language. He argued that the ReciprocalP attached in low and high applicative, yielded a Recipient meaning for the applied argument in these 68 We assume that the accusative argument does not need to move to the specifier of vP position in order to check its case. This happens via Agree of its features with the head of vP. 197 structures. However, in Georgian, the morphological evidence does not allow us to argue that the Appl0 head composes with the Reflexive like in the following Kirundi structure in (64b): (55) a. Kirundi applicative abo bagabo ba-a- rungik-ir-ye abana Those men 3p-PST-send-APPLIC-Asp children ‘Those men sent children money.’ b. Reciprocalized applicative amahara.. money Abo bagabo ba-a- rungik-ir-an-ye amahara. Those men 3p-PST-send-APPLIC-AN-Asp money Those men sent money to each other /people arb. (Ndaiyragije 2006: 288) c. The structure for (55b) VoiceP Men Voice’ Voice ApplP Children Appl’ Appl0 VP Send RecP PRO Rec’ Rec0 -an money As shown in these sentences, reciprocalization of an applicative structure results in the complex morphological form which, along with the applicative marker, realizes the Reciprocal0 head: the applied argument is no longer projected due to the reciprocal 198 marker –an. Thus, PRO is generated in the RecipP as the applied argument. This proposal does not argue for high/low attachment of the Reciprocal head though. The following section illustrates other types of low applicatives where the Appl0 head has the interpretation ‘AT’ of stative possession. 3.6 Possessor Datives as low applicatives 3.6.0 Introduction Cuervo (2003) considers possessor dative arguments embedded under the stative predicates (admirar ‘admire, envidiar ‘envy’, conocer ‘know’) or non-directional activity verbs such as look ‘mira’r, ‘sostoner’ ‘hold’ as low possessor applicatives. In these structures, the applied argument is licensed by a low applicative head and this argument is related to the theme as a ‘stative’ possessor. As dative arguments in DOCs, these dative arguments bear no direct relation to the event. The analysis of such low applicatives presupposes the merger of a distinct type of Appl0 head that establishes a static relation between the applied argument and the theme, but crucially not dynamic transfer-ofpossession. The syntactic structure of applicatives formed with such events results from the merger of low applicative head with the Root that is embedded under the dynamic event-introducing head vDO (wash, kiss), static event introducer vBE, or dynamic unaccusative vGO head. With these structures we find the static possession between the dative argument and the theme mediated through the configuration of the dative argument as the specifier of ApplP and the theme as the complement of the Root. The following structure illustrating these relations in possessor datives is adapted from Cuervo (2003): (56) Structure for possessor datives 199 a. Voice P DPsubj Voice’ Voice vP v VP Root ApplP DP applied arg. b.[VoiceP DPsubj [ Voice [vP Appl’ Appl0 DPobj (Cuervo 2003) v [VP root [ApplP DPapplied [ Appl0 DPobj]]]]]] The goal of this section is to present empirical evidence for this hypothesis. First, stative psychological verbs with the event head vBE are discussed, and then those of nondirectional activity verbs (wash, kiss, hold, etc.) 3.6.1 Low applicatives of stative eventualities Examining some stative verbs in Georgian such as love, know, etc, it appears that some verbs fail to project dative applied arguments, even though genitive possessor arguments are felicitous with those structures: (57) Genitive possessors with stative events a. dato-s shurs ketevan-is motmineba D-Dat envies K-Gen patience ‘Dato envies Ketevan’s patience.’ b. datom icis ninos adgilsamq’opel-i. D-Erg knows N-Gen whereabouts-Nom ‘Dato knows Nino’s whereabouts.’ c.*dato-s shurs ketevan-s D-Dat envies K-Dat ‘Dato envies Ketevan’s patience.’ motmineba. patience 200 d. deda-m eliso- s k’aba da- uc’una. Mother-Erg E-Dat dress prev- APPLIC- disapprove ‘Mother disapproved of Eliso’s dress.’ e. nino-m Salome-s p’erangi mo- uc’ona N-Erg S-Dat shirt prev- APPLIC- liked ‘Nino liked Salome’s shirt.’ The stative event shown in (57b) does not project the dative argument while the psychological verbs in (57a, d & e) do. The following non-directional activity verbs also project dative arguments denoting the possessor relation with their themes: (58) Non-directional activities and statives a. ekim-ma pacient-s chriloba doctor-Erg patien-Dat wound ‘A doctor cured a patient’s wound.’ b. ekim-ma pacient’-s ch’riloba doctor-Erg patient-Dat wound ‘A doctor healed a patient’s wound.’ c. nana-m eka-s chanta N-Erg E-Dat bag ‘Nana held Eka’s bag.’ mo- urchina 69. prev- APPLIC- cure umkurnala APPLIC- healed da- uchira prev- APPLIC- hold Note that in (58), both psychological and non-directional activity verbs form low applicatives where the relation between the applied dative argument and the theme is one of inalienable or alienable possession. The morphological realization of the Appl0 head is i-/u- , which is sensitive to the phi-features of the dative possessor argument. The relevant question might be why some psych verbs can form low applicative relation while others cannot. Recall from the chapter two of this dissertation, that in Georgian and related languages, three types of psych verbs were identified in terms of 69 Note that some of these verbs take the preverbal morphemes to mark perfective aspect, while some as in (68b) does not. This property can be correlated with the lexical semantics of these verbs and since it is not relevant for present purposes I will not pursue its analysis here. 201 their event semantics. They were called activities, state, and dynamic passives. Their morphological idiosyncrasy correlated nicely with the syntactic and semantic properties of experiencers in these contexts. The experiencers of activities were interpreted as voluntary subjects while involuntary subjects appear in state and dynamic passives. Here is an example of the verb ‘like’, which can express only two types of semantics: (59) a. State mo- m- c’ons prev- 1S- like ‘I like X.’ b. Activities v- ic’on- eb 1S- REFL- like- TH ‘I am liking X.’ Notice that this predicate does not form a dynamic passive. The prefix i- in activities presumably marks the Refl0 head because it is not sensitive to the phi-features of both arguments. The i-/u- allomorphs show up in the applicative structure when the dative applied argument (in these structures, the possessor) is introduced by the Appl0 head. Thus, the psychological verbs forming the low applicative relation in (57d & e) express an activity rather than a state. The activity psychological verbs like, approve, etc. in their active meaning can express a low applicative relation between the dative applied argument and the theme. Crucially, this relation is that of static possession denoting AT, but not Recipient (to) and Source (from). The stative counterparts of like and approve cannot add the applied dative argument as shown in the following: (60) State psychological predicates a. me I-Dat ketevan-is k-Gen motmineba patience momc’ons. like 202 ‘I like Ketevan’s patience.’ b.* me ketevan-s motmineba momc’ons. I-Dat k-Dat patience like These sentences illustrate that state psychological predicates resist applicativization. Low possessor applicatives (AT) of Spanish have corresponding Georgian counterparts expressed by the psychological verbs of activities, which involve the active event head vDO rather than the vBE head: (61)a. v- c’on- u- eb 1S- APPLIC- approve- TH Lit: ‘I approve it for somebody.’ 70 b. VoiceP Voice’ DPNOM/ERG Voice0 vPDO VP ApplP DPDAT possessor vDO Vroot Appl’ DPACC theme Appl0 i-/u- I argue that the reason why state verbs cannot add the applied arguments is that their experiencer subjects are assigned an inherent dative case in the specifier of the ApplP. Since the structural position of the dative experiencer argument is the spec of ApplP, there is no place for the applied argument to be projected. This is a tentative conclusion based on the structural positions of dative experiencers. 70 Note that this translation in English does not represent an applicative relation since the Benefactee argument is marked with the preposition. 203 3.6.2 Other activity verbs in applicative constructions Non-directional activity verbs such as cure, heal, and hold can also add dative arguments and express a stative low applicative relation between the applied dative argument and the theme. These dative arguments are added via an Appl0 head. I analyze the structure of applicatives formed with these verbs below and argue that it includes the vDO of activity event type above the ApplP, which relates the dative argument to the theme. The meaning of this relation is interpreted as one of stative possession (AT) much like in the activity psychological verbs shown in the preceding section. Crucially, these non-directional activities also owe their semantics to vDO . The Roots like hold, heal, cure can be embedded under this event head and receive activity reading. The subjects are interpreted as voluntary agents and are assigned nom/erg/dative cases across series. The dative applied argument can be added through the low Appl0 head and this argument bears stative possession (AT) to the theme. The following derivation illustrates the mentioned semantic and syntactic properties of low applicatives: (62) The low applicative of ‘hold’ a. me dato-s chanta I-Erg. D-Dat. bag-Acc ‘I held Dato a bag.’ da- v- uch’ire Prev- 1S- APPLIC- hold 204 b. VoiceP DPNOM/ERG Ext.arg. ‘me’ I Voice’ VP ApplicP Dat Appl.arg Voice0 vP vDO V0 chir ‘hold’ Appl’ DPACC Appl0 Theme i-/u ‘chanta’ bag I assume that the case checking relations in these structures is the same as in DOCs where the Recipient and Source applied arguments where projected. However, in the following example observe that the same verb hold, denoting a stative eventuality, cannot add a dative applied argument and form the low applicative because the dative argument is projected as a subject of such verb: (63) Stative eventuality of hold impossible in an applicative construction a.* me ketevan-s chanta I-Dat K-Dat bag ‘I am holding Ketevan’s bag.’ b. me ketevan-is chanta I-Dat K-Gen bag ‘I am holding Ketevan’s bag.’ m- ich’iravs 1S- APPLIC- hold m- ich’iravs 1S- APPLIC- hold As seen in (63b), only the genitive possessor structure is available for the stative interpretation of hold. However, the morpheme inserted into the pre-base position in (63b) is sensitive to the phi-features of the dative subject and this prompts me to suggest that the structure will be interpreted as a high applicative below. 205 Georgian fits the class of languages, which selects for a low applicative head and can express Recipient, Source, and stative Possessor relations between the applied dative argument and the theme. However, in contrast to Spanish, the low applicatives are not available for stative eventualities, and even Roots, which typically show up in stative contexts in other languages, in Georgian appear to form applicatives only with activity semantics. Moreover, it has been shown that applicative relations can exist not only in DOCs or psychological predicates, but in a wider variety of syntactic contexts, such as inchoative, NI and AI environments, and reflexive Voice contexts. The morphological realization of the Appl0 head is uniform across different constructions where Appl0 head takes different types of vP complements. 3.7 Four-place predicates as hybrid type applicatives 3.7.0 Introduction Four-place predicates present an interesting case of applicatives combining high and low applicative relations in the same structure as well as high applicative relation with path conflation. Some of these predicates project a location/locatum argument which thematically is interpreted as a location or the stative possessor of the theme. First, observe empirical facts: (64) Four-place predicates in Georgian a. man me anzor-s c’erili He/she me-Dat A-Dat letter ‘He wrote a letter for me to Anzor.’ b. man me k’aba-s ɣili he/she me-Dat dress-Dat button ‘He/she stitched a button to the dress fro me.’ mim- ic’era. prev- 1O- APPLIC- wrote mi- m- ik’era prev-1O-APPLIC- stitched 206 c. man shen statia-s abzaci he you-Dat article-Dat paragraph ‘He/she typed you a paragraph to the article.’ mi- g- ibech’da. prev- 2O- APPLIC- typed d. man me mat manipesti He me-Dat them-Dat manifesto ‘He addressed them with the manifesto for me.’ mi- m- imarta. prev- 1O- APPLIC- addressed e. man shen p’erang-s naxat’i He you-Dat shirt-Dat picture ‘He glued you the picture to the shirt.’ mi- gic’eba. prev- 2O- APPLIC- glued f. man shen kedel-s surati he you-Dat wall-Dat picture ‘He painted the picture for you on the wall.’ g. man shen kurtuk’-s pasi He/she you-Dat jacket-Dat price Lit: ‘He lowered you the price of the jacket.’ mi- g- ixat’a. prev- 2O- APPLIC- painted da- gik’lo. prev- 2O- APPLIC- dicrease Notice that the two dative arguments in these structures have different meanings: the higher one being interpreted as a Benefactee of an event performed by the Agent, while the lower dative argument is interpreted either as a location (64b, c, e & f) or the Recipient/Possessor of the theme (64a, d & g) 71. It is of interest to note that in Georgian, the differential thematic interpretations of these lower dative arguments is associated with the animacy of nominals projected in this low position. In (65), observe that animate dative arguments alternate with the locatives marked with the postposition –ze ‘on’, while inanimate datives with the nouns marked with the postposition –tvis ‘for’/’to’: (65) Postposional marking of lower dative arguments associated with animacy: a. man He/she 71 me me-Dat Anzor-tan Anzor-Dat.to c’erili letter mi- m- ic’era. prev- 1O- APPLIC- wrote The lower dative arguments in all these structures freely alternate with the postpositional adjuncts denoting LOCATIONS or Recipients as shown in (61). 207 ‘He wrote a letter for me to Anzor.’ b. man me k’aba-ze ɣili he/she me-Dat dress-Dat.on button ‘He/she stitched a button to the dress fro me.’ mi- m- ik’era prev-1O- APPLIC- stitched c. man shen statia-ze abzaci he you-Dat article-Dat.on paragraph ‘He/she typed you a paragraph to the article.’ mi- g- ibech’da. prev- 2O- APPLIC- typed d. man me mat-tan manipesti He me-Dat them-Dat.to manifesto ‘He addressed them with the manifesto for me.’ e. man shen p’erang-ze naxat’i He you-Dat shirt-Dat.on picture ‘He glued you the picture to the shirt.’ f. man shen kedel-ze surati he you-Dat wall-Dat.on picture ‘He painted the picture for you on the wall.’ g. man shen kurtuk’-ze pasi He/she you-Dat jacket-Dat.on price Lit: ‘He lowered you the price of the jacket.’ mi- m- imarta. prev-1O- APPLIC- addressed mi- gic’eba. prev- 2O- APPLIC- glued mi- g- ixat’a. prev- 2O- APPLIC- painted da- g- ik’lo. prev- 2O- APPLIC- decrease This difference in postpositional marking shows the correlation between postpositional case marking with the animacy and thematic interpretations of these lower arguments: animate arguments are interpreted as RECIPIENTS or Possessors (61g) as opposed to inanimates, which are interpreted as LOCATIONS. This kind of correlation between the case marking and semantic interpretations of arguments is not unique. Jelinek (1999) and Jelinek & Carnie (2003) show that in Yaqui (Hiaki, an Uto-Aztecan language spoken in Sonora, Mexico, and Arizona), the arguments of ditransitive verbs allow their internal arguments are marked either with the accusative/dative or the accusative/accusative cases 208 depending on semantic interpretations of these arguments. Such verbs include ‘give’, ‘teach’, ‘borrow’, and ‘take’. Here is an example including ‘give’: (66)a. ‘aapo Huan-tau ‘uka vachi-ta he John-Dat Det.Acc corn-Acc ‘He gave John the corn.’ b. ‘aapo Huan-ta ‘uka vachi-ta he John-Acc Det.Acc corn-Acc ‘He gave John the corn (as a gift).’ maka-k (Acc/Dat) give-Perf miika-k (Acc/Acc) give.food-Perf (Jelinek & Carnie 2003:273) Jelinek & Carnie argue that the differential case marking on the goal DP induces distinct semantics. Namely, the acc/dative pattern is similar to English to-dative constructions with the location interpretation of dative argument, while the verbs that require the double-accusative marking must have animate goals and the dative argument be interpreted as ‘strongly affected’ by the action of the Agent. The “strongly affected” meaning of John is actually being fed the corn. A similar parallelism between the case marking in double-object constructions (DOCs) and semantic interpretations of dative arguments is detected in Korean (Jung & Miyagawa 2004, henceforth, J & M). J & M base their analysis of Korean ditransitive structures on Harley’s (2002) proposal of give as a verb with two possible decomposition scenarios: according to her, as argued in Section 3.2 of this dissertation, give in the DOC John gave Mary the book has the meaning John CAUSED Mary to HAVE a book and this interpretation is associated with two functional elements: CAUSE and PHAVE, the latter being interpreted as HAVE 72. In its prepositional version, John gave a book to Mary the 72 Pylkkanen (2002) is not sympethatic with the small clause analysis of DOCs (Guéron, 1986, Hoekstra, 1988, Harley, 2000) which treat DOCs as types of causatives taking the Goal predicate as a complement. 209 PLOC is interpreted as LOCATION 73. The conclusion drawn about ditransitive structures cross-linguistically is that double-object and to-dative constructions can be decomposed into CAUSE and PHAVE /PLOC components in different languages such as English and Korean. Additionally in Korean, like in the Hiaki examples above, there is a correlation between the case-marking of goal arguments and their semantic interpretation. In DOCs, Goals are marked with the accusative case creating double-accusative marking for internal arguments. The accusative applied argument has obligatory specific interpretation. J & M suggest that this ‘obligatory specificity’ is a corollary of double accusative marking by CAUSE in these contexts. In locative structures, Goals are marked with dative and they are not interpreted as specific. Observe the following structures adapted from J & M (2004): (67) Double Object Construction (DOC) a. Mary-ka John-ul chayk-ul cwu-ess-ta. Mary-Nom J-Acc book-Acc give-Past-Dec ‘Mary gave John a book.’ (Jung & Miyagawa 2004:17) b. vP SUBJ PP GoalACC v’ v0 CAUSE P’ ThemeACC PHAVE Pylkkanen argues that this type of analysis is good for give but not for other DOCs given contrasts like: #I broke the vase but it didn’t break, or DOC: I wrote Sue the letter but she never got it, etc. 73 The analysis of HAVE as a preposition rather than a verb have been discussed by many authors (Benveniste 1966, Freeze 1992, Gueron 1995, & Kayne 1993). The details of their analysis are irrelevant here. 210 (68) To-Locative construction a. mary-ka John-eykey Mary-Nom John-Dat ‘Mary gave a book to John.’ b. chayk-ul book-Acc cwu-ess-ta give-Past-Dec vP Subj v’ v0 CAUSE PP GoalDAT P’ ThemeACC PLOC As said above, no specific meaning is available for the Locative argument in (68). These observations on the argument structure of ditransitives may be of relevance for analyzing Georgian four-place predicates illustrated in (65). 3.7.1 Analysis of morphosyntax of four-place applicatives As indicated above, the higher dative arguments are Benefactees. I interpret the relation between this high dative argument and an event as a high applicative in which no transfer-of-possession obtains between two arguments. Given these observations, I argue that in Georgian four-place verbs, animacy is key to the Recipient/possessor versus Location interpretations of lower dative arguments. Following Harley and J & M, I propose that in the structures where the lower dative arguments are animates and marked with the postposition –tan, these dative arguments are interpreted as Recipients much like accusative arguments in Korean by PHAVE, while inanimate dative arguments correspondingly marked with –ze postposition can be interpreted as Locations projected by PLOC. 211 Also, as mentioned above, the higher dative argument in (65g) is interpreted as the Benefactee of an event performed by an external argument. I suggest that the lower dative argument in (65g) thematically can be interpreted as stative possessor of the theme. I conceptualize the relation between this lower dative and the theme arguments with the low applicative head introducing the possessor dative argument. The stative possession relation may be introduced by the event head vBE (of stative possession) as argued by Cuervo (2003) for Spanish psychological predicates and in Sections 3.6 and 3.8 of this dissertation for certain classes of Georgian verbs. The external argument of this construction is projected by the Voice head and the case of this argument checked against this head. Therefore, the structure in (61g) may be decomposed in the following way: (69)a. man shen kurtuk’-s pasi He/she you-Dat jacket-Dat price Lit: ‘He lowered you the price of the jacket.’ da- g- ik’lo. prev- 2O- APPLIC- decrease 212 VoiceP SUBJNOM/ERG Man ‘he /she’ Voice’ Voice0 vP ApplPHIGH Appl’ DPDAT ‘me’ I Appl0 i-, u- vP VP ApplP CAUSE a- vBE V0 kl ‘lower’ Appl’ DPDAT possessor DPACC Appl0 Theme This is a hybrid type applicative structure combining two applicative heads: high and low and two vPs one being a CAUSE and another, the stative event-introducer vBE. It is the latter v0 head that is responsible for stative possession relation between the lower dative argument and the theme. Another question to ask is which head is realized with the i-/ u- affixes. In low applicatives, discussed so far, the low applicative head was realized with this allomorphy. Now observe the following data, which shows that i-/u- is sensitive to higher dative argument, i.e. Benefactee: (70) The paradigm of 4-place predicate ‘write’ a. datom me ek’a-s c’erili D-Erg me-Dat E-Dat letter ‘Dato wrote me the letter to Ek’a.’ mi- m- ic’era. prev- 1O- APPLIC- wrote 213 b. datom shen ek’a-s c’erili D-Erg you-Dat E-Dat letter ‘Dato wrote you the letter to Ek’a.’ c. dato-m ma-s ek’as c’erili D-Erg him-Dat E-Dat letter ‘Dato wrote him/her the letter to Ek’a.’ mi- g- ic’era. prev- 2O- APPLIC- wrote mi- uc’era. prev- APPLIC- wrote The VI for the Appl0 head is sensitive to the person feature of the higher dative argument, i.e. the Benefactee projected by the high Appl0 head. Therefore, I assume that only the high Appl0 head is realized in these constructions. This can be expected given templatic constraints on the realization of argument structure-changing morphemes in the Georgian verb template. Therefore, the insertion of the second set of i-/u- affixes is prevented. The morphological realization of these hybrid type applicatives with two Appl0 heads is no different from that of the low applicative head in DOCs. The case marking of the four arguments in these structures is of interest because the two dative cases checked on the Benefactee and Recipient arguments are structural as they both change into the postpositional genitive or dative in the Perfective series. I assume that these dative cases are checked against the applicative heads that introduce them. The accusative case on the theme may be checked against v0 head the same way as it was argued for the low Recipient and Source applicatives above. Now the structures for the rest of four-place predicates will be analyzed. As mentioned above, in (65a-f) the two dative arguments are projected the higher one receiving the Benefactee thematic interpretation while the lower one either Recipient or Location depending on the animacy. Following Harley (2002) and J & M (2004), I claim that these relations in (66) can be decomposed in two types of PPs, which embed two 214 postpositional DPs in their specifiers one being interpreted as HAVE with the animate DP and another as LOCATION with inanimate. Here is the structure showing these interpretations of lower applied arguments: (71) VoiceP Voice’ SUBJNOM/ERG Voice0 vP ApplPHIGH DPDAT ‘me’ I Appl’ Appl0 i-, u- vPDO VP PP DPACC P’ theme DPDAT/POST Location/ Recipient CAUSE a- vDO V0 write, glue, etc. PHAVE/ PLOC The higher dative argument has high applicative relation with the event and it is introduced by the Appl0 head merging above VP. The structural dative of this argument is presumably checked against the Appl0 head. The lower applied argument is in the sister position of the P head which may be considered as functional rather than lexical and following various researchers (Hale & Keyser 2002 among them). The oblique postpositional cases do not require checking and the accusative of the theme may be checked against the v0 head via Agree because no other argument intervenes between them to incur the minimality violation. 215 The morpheme order in these four-pace predicates is subject to linearization rules which may be language-specific, governed by morphological well-formedness conditions (as argued in the introduction). As shown in (71), only one high applicative head is merged in these structures and its morphological exponent bleeds the exponent realizing the CAUSE due to constraints imposed on the spellout of argument structure-changing morphemes. 3.8 High Applicatives in Georgian 3.8.0 Introduction This section on high applicatives focuses on dative arguments that do not relate to the theme, but rather to an event expressed by the verb. Cross-linguistically, such structures express three types of semantics (Cuervo 2003), which are distinguished by the type of the vP complement that the Appl0 head takes: stative vPBE, a dynamic non-agentive vPGO or a dynamic agentive vPDO. Languages differ as to how many of these heads may be selected. They may select one, two or all three vP complements. In 3.8.1 I develop an analysis of applicative constructions whose head selects for the stative vPBE complement. The psychological state verbs like love, like, hate, etc. are analyzed as high applicatives due to their morphological shape and the relation of the dative argument with the event. The section does not focus on the activity psychological verbs which have been shown above to take vDO and form low applicatives. In 3.8.2, applicative structures taking vPGO, i.e. non-agentive dynamic events will be analyzed moxda ‘happen’, chamouvida ‘arrive’, mouvida ‘occur to somebody,’ gamouvida ‘appear’, etc. Some of these structures are argued to show low applicative meaning 216 (‘arrive for somebody, got/receive something). Section 3.8.3 analyzes those dynamic agentive events (walk, dance) that are argued to have high applicative meanings across many languages (Pylkkanen 2002, Jeong 2007 among others). The semantic interpretation of dative arguments varies in these structures, sometimes showing benefactive, and sometimes malefactive meanings. 3.8.1. High applicatives with stative unaccusative predicates In Georgian, the morphological shape of psychological predicates with stative interpretations includes the applicative morpheme, which is sensitive to the person feature of the dative Experiencer argument: (72) State psychological verbs: a. me q’vavileb-i I-Dat flowers-Nom ‘I love flowers.’ m- iq’var- s. 1S- APPLIC- love- 3O b. shen q’vavilebi g- iq’var- s. you-Dat flowers 2S- APPLIC- love- 3O ‘You love flowers.’ c. mas q’vavilebi uq’var- s. he/she-Dat flowers APPLIC- love- 3O ‘He/she loves flowers.’ This paradigm shows that the allomorphy associated with the Appl0 head is sensitive to the person features of dative experiencer arguments much like with the dative applied arguments in DOCs. Dative arguments may also be interpreted as locatives or inalienable possessors as shown in (73): (73) Experiencer dative argument a. m- inda 1S- APPLIC- want ‘I want X.’ 217 b. g - inda 2- APPLIC- want ‘You want X.’ c. unda APPLIC- want ‘He/she wants X.’ (74) Locative dative arguments: a. me pexi m- ichans I-Dat foot-Nom 1S- APPLIC- seen Lit: ‘I have my foot seen.’ 74 b. shen pexi g- ichans you-Dat foot 2S- APPLIC- seen Lit: ‘You have your foot seen.’ c. mas pexi uhe/she-Dat foot APPLICLit: ‘He/she has her foot seen.’ chans seen The dative argument in (73) is interpreted as an involuntary experiencer, while in (74) as an inalienable possessor of the theme, although the English translation does not render the meaning of this Georgian verb adequately. The interpretation is that the part of the body or the property of the dative argument ‘is seen’ and the applied dative argument is interpreted as a possessor of the property or the body part denoted by the theme. Observe the metaphorical possessor meaning of this relation: (75) ‘Seen’ locative ninos motminebas sazɣvari ar uchans. N-Gen patience-Dat boundary not APPLIC- have/seen ‘Nino’s patience does not have a boundary.’ (Lit: The boundary of Nino’s patience is not/cannot be seen.’ 74 These free translations are awkward in English but this is only interpretations of these Georgian structures. 218 In both (73) and (74), the dative DP is assumed to be introduced by the Appl0 head, but there is a clear sense that the relation between the dative argument with the theme in love and want is different from that in seen. In the former, the Experiencer argument does not bear either Recipient, or Source or Possessor meaning, while in ‘seen’ the dative argument is a location whose integral part is the theme. Thus, it can be argued that the structures in (73)-(74) encode a high applicative relation between the dative argument and an event while the applicative in (74) is interpreted as low because the relation of the dative argument with the theme is one of part/whole or stative possession. I follow Cuervo (2003) in these interpretations of the high vs. low distinction and propose that locative/possessor datives can be analyzed as low applicatives where the head is the complement of a stative vPBE. By contrast, the experiencer dative DPs are projected by a high Appl0 head that takes a stative vPBE (i.e. vBE) as its complement. Thus, the structures of high applicatives can be sketched the following way: (76)a. k’ato-s uqvars/unda K-Dat APPLIC- loves/wants ‘k’ato loves/wants the ice-cream.’ b. naq’in-i. ice-cream-Nom ApplP Appl’ DPDAT K’ato vPBE DPNOM ice-cream VP Appl0 v’ V0 -nda, q’var want, love, etc. vBE 219 In this configuration, the theme DP is in the specifier of the event head and is not related to the higher dative argument through the Appl0 head 75. In the low applicative with the stative predicate the configuration is different since the dative experiencer and the theme are projected as the specifier and the complement of the Appl0 head. This configuration ensures that the semantics of part/whole or possession between the theme and the dative argument is syntactically established. Here is the structure: (77) Low applicative of Locative a. nino-s uchans N-Dat APPLIC- seen ‘Lit: ‘Nino’s foot is seen/appears.’ b. pexi. foot vPBE VP V0 chans ‘seen’/’appear’ ApplicP DPDAT nino vBE Applic’ DPACC pexi ‘foot’ Applic0 i-/u- These structures show the necessity of careful elaboration of the diagnostic tests for high and low applicatives when seeing such subtle distinctions in meaning in state psychological and locative predicates. Structurally, dative arguments are very similar to each other both in high and low positions because they are the highest arguments of the clause and move to the subject position. The morphological properties of high 75 Note the position of Nom theme in this structures. I assume that this case cannot be assigned in headsister relation with V0. Therefore, the position of the Nom object can be in the spec of VP. 220 applicatives are no different from low ones because the head is also realized with the allomorphy i-/u-. The evidence then for the different positions is purely semantic. 3.8.2 High applicatives of other unaccusative predicates This section presents a range of high applicative constructions where the Appl0 head takes a vGO complement (i.e. unaccusative verbs with change-of-state meaning or the verbs of happening). In these structures, no direct relation exists between the dative argument and the theme, but between the dative argument and an event such relation does obtain: (78) High applicative above unaccusative verb a. mak’a-s cudi ambavi M-Dat bad thing-Nom ‘Something bad happened to Mak’a.’ mo- uxda. prev- APPLIC- happened b. elene-s c’q’ali gadmo- uvida E-Dat water prev- APPLIC- flow.over Lit: ‘Water overflew from the casserole on Elene.’ kvabi-dan. casserole.from The dative arguments in these sentences are not in any way related to the themes: Mak’a to something bad and Elene to water. Both applicatives have a malefactive reading. The allomorphy i-/u- is again sensitive to the person feature of the dative argument. High applicative meaning is encoded in the ApplP taking a dynamic vGO as its complement and this syntax is associated with the relation between the dative argument (subject) and an event adversely affecting this argument. In (78b), the Root of the motion verb –vid ‘go’ expresses the movement of an inanimate entity from the designated location. The dative argument does not bear the possession relation with the water in this context: 221 (79) High applicative of unaccusative verb: a. mak’a-s cudi ambav-i M-Dat bad thing-Nom ‘Something bad happened to Mak’a.’ b. mo- uxda. prev- APPLIC- happened VoiceP ApplP Voice0 - DP Appl’ Dat Appl0 mak’a vPGO i-/uVP vGO DPNOM V0 Theme xda, etc. Something ‘ambavi’ ‘happen’ The crucial aspect that distinguishes unaccusative verbs forming high applicatives from those unaccusatives that form low ones is whether the dative argument gets/receives the theme directly or metaphorically. If dative argument ‘receives’ the theme, then it would form low applicative relation though. Compare: (80) Applicatives with unaccusative verbs a. nino-s mama chamo- uvida N-Dat father prev- APPLIC- arrived ‘Nino’s father arrived for Nino.’ b. tekle-s saxe-ze pucuxebi T-Dat face.on pimples ‘Tekle got pimples on her face.’ gamo- uvida. prev- APPLIC- came.out Notice that ‘arrive’ may express a low applicative meaning by relating the two individuals (Nino and the father) to each other as the recipient and theme. Crucially, both arguments are projected under the vP so that the low Recipient relation between the 222 nominative theme (father) and the dative Recipient (Nino) argument. As I have argued above in Sections 3.3. & 3.4, although the position of nominative theme is low, it checks the case against T0 without incurring the minimality violations. The dative argument is introduced by the Appl0 head checking its case as well: (81) The structure for (80a) vP VP ApplP DPDAT nino vGO V0 vida ‘arrive’ Appl’ Appl0 i-/uSimilarly, the structure in (80b) is analyzed as a low applicative with the same vGO DPNOM taken as a complement in ‘overflow’, and in this structure, the Appl0 head relates the dative and theme arguments as a part/whole. Note that these distinctions in applicative meaning are not associated with a change in morphology, namely in the marking of the high vs. low applicative heads. The general picture of applicative morphology in Georgian and related languages is not complex, but it still shows mismatches between the syntax-semantics and the morphological components of the language. Both high and low applicative semantics can be obtained via the same affixation or even with the zero applicative marker in elsewhere contexts. The mismatch between these components of language can be due to many factors. One such factor is language-specific constraints on realization of argument-structure changing morphemes in the pre-base and post-base positions of the verbal template. 223 3.8.3 High applicatives with dynamic activity verbs One of the tests to distinguish between high and low applicatives in Pylkkanen (2002, 2008) is whether the Appl0 head can combine with dynamic unergative verbs like walk, dance, etc. The following sentence with the high applicative head projecting dative benefactee argument illustrates that Luganda selects for the high applicative head: (82) High applicative in Luganda: mukasa ya- tambu- ledde M PAST. walk. APPL. PAST ‘Mukasa walked for Katonga.’ katonga. K The same diagnostics can be applied to Georgian dynamic action verbs such as dance, ran, etc. and it appears that it is possible to form high applicative structures with dative arguments as Benefactees. However, it is important to note that although these structures contain canonically intransitive verbs, in the applied structures with these verbs, there is in fact an accusative Theme present: (83) High applicatives in Georgian a. nik’o-m natia-s maratoni N-Erg N-Dat marathon ‘Nik’o ran marathon for Natia.’ b. lado-m mak’a-s mteli ɣame L-Erg M-Dat all night ‘Lado danced all night long for Maka.’ c. dato-m nadia-s burti D-Erg N-Dat ball ‘Dato rolled Nadia the ball.’ ga- urbina. prev- APPLIC- ran ucek’va. APPLIC- danced ugor - av- a. APPLIC- rolled- TH- 3O 224 In these constructions, the dative arguments can be interpreted as benefactees of the events performed by the external arguments. More precisely, it is in the dative argument’s interests that the action is completed by the external argument. Such situations may well exist in the world but note the presence of theme arguments in some of the above structures. Their presence is necessary in order for the structures in (83a & c) to be well-formed. I would rather argue that in no sense the dative arguments ‘receive’ or ‘possess’ these themes. In Spanish, the constructions equivalent to (83a & b) are considered low applicatives since the beneficiary is not directly related to the event but to the theme. I depart from an analysis of these structures as low because the relation between the dative argument and the theme does not fall into any of the low applicative meanings such as recipient, source, or possessor. In (83a), Natia is a beneficiary of the event performed by the external argument. Nik’o but crucially she does not relate to ‘marathon’ as a possessor, source, or as a recipient. The same can be said of Mak’a in (83b). Even when the theme argument is restored in the structure—and it could be a certain kind of dance such as polka, tango, or waltz—the relation between Mak’a and the theme cannot be expressed. (83c) is a case in which the dative argument is interpreted as the Benefactee. Crucially, Nadia is not a Recipient of the ball because the event is not directed towards her in any sense, rather only for her benefit. Thus, again the relation is between the external argument and the event. Another suggestion for these constructions is that the change-of-state verbs whose roots often form unergative structures (dance, scream, roll, etc.) may be used transitively by adding themes and such transitives may involve the merger of the high applicative 225 head which relates the external argument to an event rather than two individuals—the dative benefactee with the theme. If this analysis of above structures is tenable, I will assume that high applicatives can be expressed by transitive verbs of change-of –state. For the purposes of comparison with Spanish high applicatives, it should be noted that dative arguments in this language are not overtly expressed in certain high applicative structures and only the clitic indicates their presence. Cuervo uses the terms ‘datives of interest’ or ‘ethical datives’ to refer to such implicit DPs in high applicatives. Analyzing dative clitics as the spellout of the high applicative head, she argues that this head in Spanish is in a way ‘defective’ because it does not project a specifier. In Georgian, there is no evidence that the high applicative head is defective, since it can project the applied Benefactee argument. This argument is related to the dynamic event itself, rather than to the theme. The following sentences provide additional evidence for the high applicative head combining with the vPDO as an introducer of a dynamic event of change: (84) High applicatives a. gia-m nana-s k’art’i G-Erg N-Dat card ‘Gia played out the cards for Nana.’ ga- utamasha. prev- APPLIC- played b.policiel-ma demonstrant’-s kamari gada- uch’ira policeman-Erg demonstrator-Dat belt prev- APPLIC- flapped. ‘The policemen flapped the demostrator/protestor with the belt.’ In (84a), the applied argument Nana is in no way related to the theme argument, although the cards are played by Gia to her benefit. The dative argument (Nana) does not end up as a possessor or a ‘Benefactee’ of card play. Thus, the applicative relation is interpreted as high. (84b) is a case of interest because the theme argument is an 226 instrument of the event completed by the external argument and it is in no way related to the applied dative argument. These interpretations clearly fit the descriptions of high applicatives: (85) The high applicative of dynamic unergative verb in (83b): VoiceP DPNOM/ERG policielma policeman Voice’ Voice0 vPDO ApplP DPDAT demonstrants demonstrator vDO Appl’ VP DPACC kamari ‘belt’ Appl0 i-/u- V0 ch’ira flap, etc. In the above examples, the high Appl0 head is realized with the same allomorphy i-/u- as the low applicative. The vast majority of applicative meanings can be realized with the i-/u- and the variability in marking is only detected in the psychological verbs (love, hate, like, etc.) where the high applicative head can be realized with the i-/u- and zero exponent. 227 3.9 Applicatives in related languages (Mingrelian and Svan) 3.9.0 Introduction This section explores the morphosyntax of applicative constructions in Mingrelian and Svan in sections 3.9.1 and 3.9.2 based on the existing literature on these languages. The primary sources that I will refer to are Otar Kajaia’s (2001) “Mingrelian-Georgian Dictionary” with a grammar synopsis of Mingrelian and Varlam Topuria’s (1967) “Grammar of the Svan Language” written in a traditional grammar framework. The main research questions with respect to applicative constructions in these languages are primarily descriptive, i.e. whether they can express the same range of applicative meanings as we have seen in Georgian and how the syntax-semantics of these structures interacts with the morphology. I will be assuming the DM framework to account for syntax-semantics and morphology mismatches in these languages. 3.9.1 Applicatives in Mingrelian Kajaia’s grammatical note on Mingrelian outlines three types of applicative relations, which he refers to as version, the term used in traditional Kartvelian Linguistics for the applicative relation. One type of version, called “neutral”, corresponds to regular transitive and DOCs that express no benefactor or possessor relation between the applied argument and the theme, as well as the external argument and the theme. The second type, termed “subjective”, in Kajaia’s system corresponds to reflexive applicatives. In these, the theme object is in the prospective possession relation with the external argument. The third constructions, “objective version” corresponds to high or low applicatives in which either a dynamic transfer-of-possession or source relation obtains 228 between two individuals, or the external argument simply relates to the event without specific possessor relation between it and the theme. Both high and low applicatives of transitive verbs in Mingrelian can be expressed by the same allomorphy i-/u- as in Georgian: (86) Mingrelian applicatives a. m- ibons 1O- APPLIC- wash ‘X is washing Y for me.’ b. g- ibons 2O- APPLIC- wash ‘X is washing Y for you.’ c. ubons APPLIC- wash ‘He is washing X for him/her.’ (Kajaia, 2001: 57) In these examples the i-/u- allomorphy is sensitive to the person feature of the applied argument the same way as in Georgian. I assume that the VIs competing for the insertion in the Appl0 head are the following: (87) Vocabulary Items for the Appl0 head a. i- Appl0 / [dat] [+1] [+2] ____ b. u- Appl0 / [dat] [+3] ____ c. - Appl0 / elsewhere Observe that the low applicative relation in DOCs has the same morphological marking as in Georgian: (88) Mingrelian applicatives 229 a. m- itasuns 1O- APPLIC- sow ‘X is sowing for me.’ utasuns APPLIC- sow ‘X is sowing for him/her.’ b. m- ich’ans 1O- APPLIC- sew ‘X is sews for me.’ uch’ans APPLIC- sew ‘He/she sews for him/her.’ The person feature of the applied argument in low and high applicatives is crucial for vocabulary insertion. In applicatives formed from passivization of DOCs, both low and high applicative meaning is expressed via the allomorphy i-/u- along with the passive suffix –d. In these constructions, the movement of the theme argument to the subject position of passive is impossible while that of the applied argument is acceptable: (89) Mingrelian passive applicatives a. mishkuron- du (n) 1S- APPLIC- builtpass- 3O ‘It is built for me’ (Lit: ‘I am built it.’) b. ushkuron- du (n) APPLIC- builtpass3O ‘It is built for him/her.’ (Lit: ‘He/she is built it.’) In these passive forms, the low transfer-of-possession relation between the applied argument and the theme does not change from the corresponding active structure. I suggest that the movement of the applied argument to the sentence-initial position is unobstructed because, as was noted above, the applied argument is projected higher than the theme, and asymmetrically c-commands the latter and the movement of the dative argument to sentence-initial position does not incur any minimality violation. In addition, the morphological marking reflects the changes in the syntactic structure as the suffix –d is inserted into the Voice0 head, which bears the feature [Passive]. 230 Recall that in Georgian the following applicatives formed from inchoative and unaccusative verbs are common: (90) Georgian applicatives of unaccusatives and inchoative verbs a. m- itbeba 1S- APPLIC- warm ‘It is warming up for me.’ (Lit: ‘I am being warmed up X.’) b. m- it’k’beba 1S- APPLIC- sweet ‘X is sweetened for me.’ (Lit: ‘I am being sweetened X.’) The morphological marking of these applicatives is also sensitive to the person feature of the dative applied argument, which is the subject of the construction. These structures resemble reflexive applicatives, but are different from the latter in that they are formed from internally- or externally-caused change-of-state verbs. Therefore, no external argument is projected in these structures like in applicatives of internally-caused events discussed in Section 3.3. Mingrelian allows similar applicative structures as illustrated in the following: (91) Mingrelian applicatives of change-of-state verbs a. m- it’ibu (n) 1S- APPLIC- warm.up ‘It is warming up for me’ b. g- itibu(n) 2S- APPLIC- warm.up ‘It is warming up for you.’ The subject of these predicates is not an external argument in a crucial sense and it must be marked with the dative case because it triggers the inverse agreement pattern (‘m-set’) on verbs. I claim that the structures in (91) have a low applicative. 231 The passivized applicatives in Mingrelian do not presumably involve a full cycle, as shown in the following high and low applicative structures: (92) Low applicative in Mingrelian: a. m- ishkurondu (n) 1s- APPLIC- built ‘I am built it.’ b. VoicePPASSIVE Voice0 TP T0 vPDO v’ v0 VP ApplP DPDAT V0 Appl’ DPACC Appl0 In this configuration of the argument structure, the semantic relation between the applied dative argument and the theme is that of transfer-of-possession. The dative on the applied argument is checked against the Appl head0. The accusative case of the theme is presumably checked against vDO head. Interestingly, the low applicatives of internally-changed verbs in Mingrelian are marked with i-/u- allomorphy as in (93): (93) Low applicative of internally-changed verbs in Mingrelian: a. u-t’ibu (n) ‘It is warmed up for X.’(Lit: X is warmed up Y.’) 232 b. VoiceP Voice0 vPDO v0 VP V0 ApplP Appl’ DPDAT X DPNOM Appl0 In both structures, the direct object undergoes the change-of-state and the applied argument ‘benefits’ from this event. The applicative relation is low because the dative argument is a Recipient of the theme, at least in a metaphorical sense. There is evidence that Mingrelian also has e-prefixed low applicatives parallel to those formed from internally-changed verbs in Georgian in Section 3.3. Recall that the following forms were found in Georgian: (94) Applicatives of internally changed verbs in Georgian a. m- ezrdeba 1S- VOICE- grow ‘It is growing for me.’ b. m- eteseba 1S- VOICE- sow ‘It is sowed for me.’ In Mingrelian, a similar meaning is expressed via the prefix a-, which is inserted in the pre-base position where various argument-structure changing morphemes are inserted. Observe the following forms: (95) Mingrelian applicatives of inchoative and transitive verbs 233 a. ardu-u (n) VOICE - grow‘It is grown for him/her.’ b. atasu-u (n) VOICE- sow ‘It is sown for him/her.’ c. achar-u (n) VOICE- write ‘It is written for him/her.’ d. axacku-n VOICEtill ‘It is tilled for him/her.’ The prefix a- is inserted into the Voice0 rather than in the Appl0 head. As argued in Section 3.3 for Georgian applicatives, the insertion of the VI in the Voice0 is due to the impoverishment of the person features from the Appl0 head and the result is the realization of the Voice0. Since the structures in (95b & c) resemble passivized applicatives of transitive verbs, I assume that the external argument is suppressed and the applied argument moves to the subject position. The morphological marking of the Appl0 head in Mingrelian is in many respects similar to that in Georgian: (96) VIs for the Appl0 head (Mingrelian) a. i- Applic0 LOW / [Dat] [+2] [+1] b. u- Applic0LOW / [Dat] [+3] c. - Applic0 / elsewhere Like in other languages in the family, only one morpheme can be spelled out for the Appl0 and Voice0 heads. 234 The last type of applicative construction is derived from stative and unergative verbs, and has high applicative meaning, since the applicative relation is obtained between an applied argument and an event. First, observe the empirical base in the following: (97) High applicatives formed from stative verbs in Mingrelian a. udʒu(n) APPLIC- lie ‘He is lying for X.’ (Lit: X is laid Y.’) b. udgu(n) APPLIC- stand ‘It is standing for X.’ (Lit: X is stood Y.’) c. uxe(n) APPLIC- sit ‘It is sitting for X.’ (Lit: X is sit Y.’) These examples show that presumably, stative eventualities can also express an applicative relation between the subject and event expressed through the theme undergoing the state of lying, standing, sitting, etc. The Mingrelian forms in (97) have parallel Georgian structures shown in the following: (98) Georgian applicatives formed from statives: a. uzis APPLIC- sit ‘It is standing for X.’ (Lit: X is stood Y.’) b. udgas APPLIC- stand ‘It is standing for X.’ (Lit: X is stood Y.’) c. uc’evs APPLIC- lie ‘He is lying for X.’ (Lit: X is laid Y.’) 235 Note that both in Mingrelian and Georgian, the VI is inserted into the Appl0 head is again sensitive to the person features of the dative argument, which is the subject in these constructions. Unfortunately, there is little evidence for high applicatives formed from unergative verbs such as dance, run, etc. in Mingrelian. The comprehensive study of applicatives in this language should involve native speakers and detailed questionnaire of fieldwork study designed to elicit a whole range of applicative relations found in Georgian in this language. 3.9.2 Applicatives in Svan Svan applicatives are similar to Georgian and Mingrelian in that they can express both the low and the high applicative relation and are morphologically realized via the i-/oallomorphy (corresponding to Georgian and Mingrelian i-/u-). The reflexive marker is the same prefix i-, which is not sensitive to the person feature of the applied argument (Topuria 1967). It may be assumed that this s- is a Voice marker inserted into the Voice head due to the impoverishment of person features on the Appl0 head or the mentioned discontinuous feeding mechanism between the VIs of the Voice and the Appl0 heads. An alternative scenario for analyzing these argument structure-changing morphemes could be that the fusion rule, which applies before the Vocabulary Insertion, combines the morphemes of the Voice0 and Appl0 heads and the reflexive i- is inserted into this fused head instead of the VIs realizing the Voice0 and Applicative heads beating out other possible morphemes in a single competition. We will not pursue this scenario here but 236 this explanation may well be a case along with the impoverishment analysis proposed above. Topuria also posits another type of applicative relation referred to as sazedao (literally meaning ‘on the top’). This type of applicative (or “version”) indirectly expresses a transfer-of-possession relation between the applied argument and the theme. Morphologically realized as a prefix a-, these Recipient applicatives encode a close spatial relation between two arguments without involving the postposional marking of the applied argument, which is otherwise common on locative arguments: (99) High Svan (a dialect) low applicatives a. eǰa ečas x-ä-diäni ečas. He him/her lends it ‘He/she lends it to her/him.’ b. eǰa x- ä-bdine lemasgû ečas. He/she kindles fire him/her ‘He /she kindles fire for him/her.’ Bal-Zemouri dialect of Svan c. bepshû x-ā-mne lezûebs Child feeds food ‘A child feeds food to the hungry.’ mäjdärs. hungry Notice that in (99a) a transfer-of –possesssion relation obtains between the dative argument and the theme. (99b) can be interpreted as a high applicative predicate because the subject performs the event that the applied argument benefits from. However, the dative argument is interpreted as a Recipient of the theme again and the structure can be interpreted as a low applicative. In Georgian, the Appl0 head is realized via the i-/u- 237 allomorphy, while in Svan the VI is a- , which in Georgian has been argued to represent the marker for CAUSE in various contexts. The Georgian translation of (99c) looks like a causative predicate because the causative marker a- is inserted into the third slot of the verbal template. Therefore, I assume that the corresponding form in Svan is also causative marked with the prefix a- of causative head. Many languages combine the causative heads with the event-introducing vPs and ApplP to express the complex relations between the arguments in DOCs. Such structures have not been discussed in this dissertation, but they are found crosslinguistically and this may be such an example. The meaning can be interpreted as ‘X causes Y to become satisfied as the result of eating.’ Svan predicates in (99) can be interpreted as low applicatives but their morphological realization with the default prefix a- suggests that the prefix a- realizes CAUSE, rather than the Appl0 head, which I assume is due to the discontinuous feeding between the VIs of these functional heads. Now let’s look at the examples of i-/o- allomorphy of the Appl0 head in Svan: (100) Svan low applicatives eǰa xogem He/she 3O- APPLIC- builds ‘He/she builds house for him/her.’ kors. house The prefix x- in the above example indexes the third person argument and o- realizes the Appl0 head. The prefix x- indexes the applied argument because it is closer to the v0 head. High applicatives in Svan have the same morphological marking as low applicatives, like in other Kartvelian languages. This is illustrated in the following: 238 (101) Svan high applicatives a. x-o-xt’aûi ‘He is painting for X.’ b. x-o-ben ‘He is tying X for him/her.’ c. x-obne ‘He is beginning Y for X.’ Observe that all these forms in (101) contain the applied arguments in a direct or indirect possessor relation to the theme and therefore, a low applicative interpretation is obtained, i.e. when the subject and the event are related to each other but not two individuals per se. The last type of applicative relation that I will consider here is the one expressed by various intransitive verbs. They may have both low and high semantics, much like eprefixed applicatives in Georgian derived from internally-changed verbs. In Svan, the same prefix e- that shows up in internally-changed verbs and in passive forms where the subject is suppressed and the applied argument moves to its position: (102) Svan e– prefixed low applicatives a. m- ext’aûi 1S- voice- paint ‘I am painted X.’ b. m- eben/mi 1S- voice- tie ‘I was tied for me.’ The applicatives in (102) contain implicit subjects and are derived through passivization of active applicative structures of di-transitive verbs. However, the 239 following forms can be argued to express a high applicative relation between the subject and a stative event: (103) High applicatives of stative events in Svan a. m-e- jshx- m- i ‘X is named for me.’ (lit: ‘I am named X.’) b. x-e-g m- i ‘Something is standing for me.’ (lit: ‘I am stood X.’) The following applicatives though are formed from internally-changed verbs and may be interpreted as low applicatives: (104) Svan low applicatives a. ǰ- egûshi 2S- voice- grow ‘(Wings) grow on you.’ (Lit: ‘I am grown wings’) b. m-e-dāʒsh-i-x Lit: ‘I am blackened.’ The forms in (104) show the resultant state of some internal event that subjects undergo. The structures are interpreted as reflexives, and I assume that the prefix e- is supposedly realizing the Voice0 in these forms. There are a number of verbs that may be interpreted as adversity causatives and show close resemblance to e-prefixed high applicatives: (105) High Svan (a dialect) applicatives a. x- epxʒeni 3S- voice- scatter ‘Something was scattered on X.’ 240 b. x- ogbeni 3S- APPLIC- dirty ‘He was dirtied.’ c. x- ekûceni 3S- voice- cut ‘He is cut.’ d. m- ekûreni 3S- voice- decompose ‘It is decomposed on him/her.’ e. x- otûpeni 3S- APPLIC- lose ‘It is lost on him/her.’ The sentences in (105) are interpreted either as high or low applicatives, where the subjects are deep structure applied arguments and I assume that they are introduced by the Appl0 head giving them Source, Recipient or Benefactee interpretation. The latter arguments may have benefactive/malefactive interpretations. 3.10 Conclusions In conclusion, it can be argued that applicatives in the Kartvelian languages can be both low and high, and their morphosyntax is very similar to each other in a way that suggests the unity of functional projections in the Proto-Kartvelian. The applicative heads of both low and high varieties show the same morphological realization in all three languages, much like causatives. There are instances of transparadigmatic syncretisms across voice, applicative, and causative morphemes, which are not explored here in detail but will be considered in future research that can be conducted on voice syncretisms in these languages. Here it can be definitively argued that applicatives derived from intransitive verbs are morphologically distinct than those derived from simple transitive 241 verbs. High/low semantics is not distinguished in the morphological component as is expected from the disjunction between grammar components where syntactic, semantic, and morphological information is processed. 242 CHAPTER 4 CONCLUSIONS Causative and applicative structures in polysynthetic languages represent both syntactically and morphologically complex structures in which the syntax/semantics and the morphological realization of the functional heads may not be always straightforward. The study has attempted to show that the interaction between these components of grammar in lexical and syntactic causatives is largely determined by the variation in the complement size that the CAUSE takes in these constructions. Empirical evidence presented in the study has shown that morphological realization of the causative head is determined by whether the CAUSE takes RootP or vP complement. Given this observation, we conclude that the realization of the syntax at Morphological Structure (MS) is not entirely random but rather quite predictable in three languages: Georgian, Mingrelian and Svan. The analysis of applicative structures also showed similar evidence with respect to the interaction between the argument structure and the morphological realization of applicative heads. It became evident that various Vocabulary Items (VIs) are sensitive to the morphosyntactic features of applied arguments, i.e. those arguments, which are definitive for this type of construction. As argued in the literature on applicatives, the applied argument is the one which is added to the argument structure of transitive verbs to form a Double Object Construction (DOC) in which applicative relations can be established between this non-core applied argument and an event or the theme argument. 243 Again empirical data from Georgian and related languages illustrated the fact that the addition of an applied argument to a transitive structure results in distinct morphological realization of predicates as opposed to regular transitive structures. Specifically, the latter realize CAUSE in the third slot of the verbal template while applicatives in DOCs realize the Appl0 head instead of the CAUSE. This unambiguously illustrates the transparent interaction between the syntax of applicatives and their morphological realization. Moreover, in so called reflexive applicatives when the applicative relation such as Recipient or Benefactee is established between the external argument and the theme, the morphological realization again ‘responds’ to the distinct syntax of such constructions. In these structures, a reflexive Voice head is merged and its phonological exponent is different from the one inserted into the Appl0 head in DOCs. Similarly, in the applicatives formed from internally- and externally-caused events, the morphological realization of the structure is different allowing the exponent of the Voice head to get realized, rather than the exponent of the Appl0 head through the mechanism of discontinuous feeding. Such an interaction between the syntax and morphology of these constructions is argued to result from various morphological rules such as discontinuous feeding or impoverishment of certain features on terminal nodes in the post-syntactic component of the grammar. Overall, evidence shows that in order for distinct applicative relations to get established between two individuals (low applicative) or an individual and an event (high applicative) it is not necessary to have distinct morphology. Future research on these constructions should include the interaction between causative and applicative structures in complex constructions involving applicatives as 244 complements of syntactic causatives or vice versa. The interaction between the morphology and syntax in these complex embedding structures will shed light at the precise nature of language-specific morphological well-formedness constraints which preclude the realization of multiple exponents for the whole range of functional heads merging in these complex structures. We hope that this work is a modest starting point for the study of more complex predicate structures in these types of languages. 245 APPENDIX A Homophony across phonological exponents of various morphemes in Georgian I Phonological exponent a1. a- realizes CAUSE in lexical causatives formed from inchoative verbs such as in the following: acxobs CAUS- bakes ‘He’she bakes it.’ 2. The same exponent realizes CAUSE in syntactic causatives of X makes Y do V type: ak’ivlebs CAUS- scream ‘He/she makes X scream.’ 3. The exponent realizes the aspectual marker in past and future tense verbs denoting the endpoint of an event: atxova prev- lended ‘He/she lended X it.’ 4. The same phonological exponent at the end of the template marks non-local subject or object and in this position it is fused with the series marker: utxr- a told- 3S/Ser ‘He/she told X.’ Here are the insertion contexts of these VIs: a. a- CAUSE / a. a- CAUSE / ___ [Root-] b. a- CAUSE / ___ v0[TRANS], [DITRANS] c. a- Asp0 [Accomplishment] d.-a Tns0 + [Person] II Phonological Exponent i- 246 1. The exponent i- realizes the Appl0 head in an environment of the local dative applied arguments [1-2] person: m- icxobs 1O- APPLIC- bakes ‘He/she bakes me it.’ 2. The same exponent realizes the Reflexive Voice in reflexive verbs such as in the following: iparsavs REFL- shaves ‘He/she shaves.’ 3. The same exponent realizes the reflexive Voice in reflexive applicatives: v- icxob 1S- REFL- bake ‘I bake it for myself.’ 4. The same exponent is inserted as a thematic marker in a set of verbs as in the following: prckvn- is PeelTH- 3S/Ser ‘He/she peels it.’ 5. The same exponent realizes an intransitivity marker, which is referred to as a passive voice marker in the traditional linguistics literature: ik’bineba intrans- bite ‘He/she bites.’ Here are the environments for the insertion of these VIs: iiii- Appl / [Dat] [+1] [+3] VoiceREFL / reflexives, applicatives v[INTRANS] TH III The phonological exponent e- 247 1. The phonological exponent e- is inserted in the [NonActive] Voice of adversity causatives: m- ek’vlevineba 1S- Voice- kill ‘Something causes me to kill.’ 2. The same expoenent realizes the Voice in the applicatives of internally and externally caused verbs: m- epurčkneba 1S- Voice- blossom ‘I am blossomed it.’ 3. The same exponent marks the Voice in verbs denoting reciprocal action such as: v- elaparak’ebi 1S- Voice- talk ‘I am talking to somebody.’ 4. The same exponent realizes the Aorist marker fused with the [1-2] person subjects or objects: Daviban- e Washed- 1O/Aor ‘I washed it.’ 5. The same exponent realizes the passive Voice: m- edz’ɣvneba 1S- Voice- dedicate ‘I am dedicated it.’ Here are the insertion contexts of these VIs: e- Voice[NONACTIVE]/ causatives, applicatives e- Voice [PASSIVE] e- Voice [ACTIVE] /activities e- Tense [AORIST] + -features These are main types of syncretisms attested across various functional morphemes in Georgian 248 REFERENCES Anderson, Stephen. 1992. A-Morphous Morphology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Arad, Maya. 2003. Locality constraints on the interpretation of roots: the Case of Hebrew Denominal verbs. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 21, 737-778. Aronoff, Marc. 1976. Word-formation in Generative Grammar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Aronoff, Marc. 1994. Morphology by Itself: Stems and Inflectional Classes. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Aronson, Howard. 1990. Georgian: A Reader’s Grammar. Columbus, Ohio: Slavica Publishers. Bach, Emmon. 1986.. The Algebra of Events. Linguistics and Philosophy 9: 5-16. [Reprinted in Paul Portner and Barbara H. Partee, eds. 2002. Formal Semantics: the Essential Readings. Oxford: Blackwell]. [Reprinted in The Language of Time: a Reader. 2005. Eds., Inderjeet Mani, James Pustejovsky, and Rob Gaizauskas, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 61-69.] Baker, Mark. 1985. The mirror principle and morphosyntactic explanation, Linguistic Inquiry 16, 373-416. Baker, Mark. 1988. Incorporation: a Theory of Grammatical Function Changing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Baker, Marc.1996. The Polysynthesis Parameter. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Baker, Marc & Chris Collins. 2006. Linkers and the internal structure of vP, Natural Language and Linguistic Teory 24: 307-354. Bejar, Susana. 2000. Structural markedness in formal features: deriving interpretability. Revue Qucbecoice de Linguistique 28.1, 47-72. Bejar, Susana. 2002. Locality, Cyclicity and Markedness in Georgian Verbal morphology. Ms., University of Toronto. Bejar, Susana. 2003. Phi-syntax: a Theory of Agreement. Ph.D dissertation. University of Toronto. 249 Bejar, Susana & Rezak, Milan. 2003. Cyclic agree. Lisbon Workshop on Agreement. Univesidade Nova de Lisboa. Belletti, Adrianna & Luigi Rizzi. 1988. Psych-verbs and Theta-theory. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 6, 291-352. Bobaljik, Jonathan. 1993. On Ergativity and Ergative Unergatives. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 19. Ed. C. Phillips. Papers on Case and Agreement II. 45-88. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bobaljik, Jason & Phil Branigan. 2006. Accentric agreement and multiple case checking. In Ergativity, Emerging Issues, Eds. A. Johns et al. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer. Bonet, Eulalia. 1991. Morphology After Syntax: Pronominal Clitics in Romance languages. Ph.D Dissertation. MIT. Borer, Hagit. 1994. The projection of arguments. In Occasional Papers in Linguistics 17, ed. E.Benedicto and J.Runner, 19-48. University of Massachussetts, Amherst: GSLA. Bresnan, Joan and Lioba Moshi. 1990. Object Asymmetries in Comparative Bantu Syntax, Linguistic Inquiry 21, 147-185. Butt, Miriam. 1995. The structure of complex predicates in Urdu. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications. Butt, Miriam & Wilhelm Geuder. 2001. On the semi(lexical) status of light verbs. In Norbert Corver and Henk van Rjiemsdijk (eds.) Semi-lexical categories: the function of content words and the content of function words. Mouton, 323-369. Carmack, Stephen. 1997. Blocking in Georgian Verbal morphology. Language, 73(2): 314-38. Chomsky, Noam. 1972. Remarks on Nominalization. In Studies on semantics in generative grammar. 11-61.The Hague: Mouton. Chomsky, Noam.1995. The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Chomsky, Noam. 1998. Minimalist Inquiries: the framework. In Step by step, ed. R. Martin, D. Michaels, and J. Uriagereka, 89-155. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chomsky, Noam. 1999. Derivation by phase. Ken Hale: A life in Language, ed. M. Kenstowicz, 1-52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Complex Predicates. 1997. (eds.) A. Alsina, J.Bresnan and P.Sells. Stanford: CSLI 250 publications. Cuervo, Maria. 2003. Datives at Large. Ph.D. Dissertation. MIT. Davidson, Donald. 1967. The logical Form of Action Sentences. In N. Rescher (ed.), The Logic of Decision and Action. 81-95. University of Pittsburg Press, Pittsburgh. Davies, Henry and Hamida Demirdache, 2000. On Lexical Verb Meanings: Evidence from Salish. 97-138. Stanford, California: CSLI Publications, Center for the Study of Language and Information. Dowty, David. 1991. Thematic proto-roles and argument selection. Language 67 (3): 547-619. Embick, David. 1998. Voice and the Interfaces of Syntax. Ph.D dissertation, MIT. Embick, David and Morris Halle. 2005. On the status of stems in Morphological theory. In T. Geerts and H. Jacobs (eds.). Proceedings of Going Romance 2003. Amsterdam, NY: John Benjamins Publishing company. Embick, David & Alec Marantz. 2006. Architecture and Blocking. MS, University of Pennsylvania and MIT. Embick, David. 2009. Localism versus Globalism in Morphology and Phonology. MS., University of Pennsylvania. Embick, David. 2007. Linearization and Local Dislocation: Derivational mechanics and interactions. Linguistic Analysis 3, 303-336. Embick, David and Rolf Noyer. 2007. Distributed Morphology and the SyntaxMorphology Interface. In G. Ramchand and C. Reiss (eds.).The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Interfaces. Oxford, New-York: Oxford University Press. 290-322. Embick, David.1997. Voice systems and the Syntax/Morphology Interface. In MITWPL, H. Harley (ed.) The Proceedings of the Penn/MIT Workshop on Aspect, Argument Structure, and Events, May 1997, 1-32. Embick, David and Rolf Noyer. 2001. Movement operations after syntax, Linguistic Inquiry 32/4, 555-595. Ergativity: Emerging Issues. eds. A. Johns, D. Massam, and J. Ndayiragije. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer. Folli, Rafaella, Heidi Harley, and Simin Karimi. 2005. Determinants of event structure in 251 Persian complex predicates, Lingua 115.10, 1365-1401. Gleitman, Lyla. 1990. Structural sources of Verb meaning. Language Acquisition 1: 3-55. Ghomeshi, Jila and Diane Massam.1994. Lexical/syntactic relations without projection. Linguistic analysis 24 (3-4), 175-217. Grimshaw, Jane and Armin Mester. 1988. Light verbs and theta-marking. Linguistic Inquiry 19 (2), 205-232. Gurevich, Olga. 2006. Constructional Morphology: The Georgian Version. Ph.D. Dissertation, UC Berkeley. Hale, Ken. 2001. Navajo verb stem position and the bipartite structure of the Navajo conjunct sector. Linguistic Inquiry 32.4, 678-693. Hale, Ken and Samuel Jay Keyser. 1993. On Argument Structure and the Lexical Expression of Syntactic Relations. In The View from Building 20: Essays In Linguistics In Honor of Sylvain Bromberger, ed. K. Hale and S.J. Keyser, 53-109. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hale, Ken and Samuel Jay Keyser. 2002. Prolegomenon to a theory of argument structure. Cambridge, MA: MIT press. Halle, Morris. 1997. Distributed Morphology: Impoverishment and Fission. In MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 30. 425-449. Cambridge, MA: MIT press. Halle, Moris and Alec Marantz. 1993. Distributed morphology and the pieces of inflection. In The View from building 20, ed. Kenneth Hale and Samuel Jay Keyser, 53110. Cambridge, MA: MIT press. Halle, Moris & Alec Marantz, 1994. Some Key features of Distributed Morphology. In MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 21, 275-288. Papers on Phonology and Morphology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Harley, Heidi, 1994. Hug a tree: Deriving morphosyntactic feature hierarchy. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 21, Papers in Phonology and morphology. Eds. A. Carnie, H. Harley with T.Bures. Harley, Heidi and Rolf Noyer. 1999. Distributed Morphology, GLOT International 4:3-9. Harley, Heidi and Noyer, Rolf. 1998. Licensing in non-lexicalist lexicon: Nominalizations, vocabulary items, and the Encyclopedia. In Papers from the UPenn/MIT Roundtable on argument structure and aspect. Ed. Heidi Harley, 175-200. 252 MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 32, Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT press. Harley, Heidi, 1995. Subjects, events and licensing. Ph.D. dissertation. MIT. Harley, Heidi. 2002. Possession and the Double Object Construction. In Linguistic Variation Yearbook 2, 29-68. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company. Harley, Heidi. 2008. On the causative construction. In S. Miagawa and M.Saito (eds.) Oxford Handbook of Japanese Linguistics, New-York, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Harley, Heidi. 2002. Minimal(ish) Linking Theory. A talk given at the Maryland Minimalist Mayfest, Maryland: May 16, 2002. Harris, Alice. 1981. Georgian Syntax. London: Cambridge University Press Horwath, Julia and Tal Siloni (forthcoming). Causatives Distributed, Ms., Tel Aviv University. Jackendoff, Ray. 1990. Semantic structures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Jacobsen, W.M. 1992. The transitive structure of events in Japanese. In Studies in Japanese linguistics I. Tokyo: Kurosio publishers. Jelinek, Eloise.1999. Accent in Yaqui. With Richard Demers and Fernando Escalante. International Journal of American Linguistics. Jelinek, Aloise & Andrew Carnie. 2003. Argument hierarchies and the mapping principle. In Formal Approaches to function in grammar: In honor of Eloise Jelinek. Eds. Andrew Carnnie, Heidi Harley & Mary Willie. 265–96. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company. Jeong, Youngmi. 2007. Applicatives: Structure and interpretation from a minimalist perspective. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Linguistik Aktuell / Linguistics Today. Jung, Yeun-Jin & Shigeru Miyagawa. 2004. Decomposing Ditransitive verbs. In Proceedings of SICGG, Summer 2004, 101-120. Kajaia, Otar. 2001. Megrul-Kartuli leksikoni. [Mingrelian-Georgian Dictionary]. Tbilisi, Georgia: Nekeri. Karimi, Simin.1997. Persian complex verbs: idiomatic or compositional. Lexicology 3 (2), 273-318. Karimi-Doostan, Mohhamad-Reza. 1997. Light verbs constructions in Persian. The Ph.D 253 dissertation. University of Essex. King, Halloway Tracy. 1994. SpecAgrP and Case: Evidence from Georgian. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 22, ed. H. Harley & C. Phillips, 91-110. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the External Argument from Its Verb. In Phrase Structure and Lexicon. Eds. Johan Rooryck & Laurie Zaring, 109-138. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Kuroda, S.-Y. 1965. Causative forms in Japanese. Foundations of language 1. 30-50. Kuroda, S.-Y. 1993. Lexical and Productive causatives in Japanese: an examination of the theory of paradigmatic structure. Journal of Japanese Linguistics 5, 1-82. Larson, Richard. 1988 (1988). On the Double Object Construction. Linguistic Inquiry 19.3, 335-391. Levin, Beth and Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1995. Unaccusativity. At the Syntax-Lexical Interface.Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT press. Lieber, R. 1992. Deconstructing Morphology: Word Formation in Syntactic Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lomashvili, Leila & Heidi Harley. (In press). Phases and templates in Georgian agreement. Manning, Christopher. 1996. Ergativity. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications. Marantz, Alec. 1992. Case and Licensing. ESCOL 91: 234-53. Marantz, Alec. 1984. On the Nature of Grammatical Relations. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. Marantz, Alec. 1997. No escape from syntax: Don't try morphological analysis in the privacy of your own lexicon. In Penn Working Papers in Linguistics 4, ed. A. Dimitriadis et al. 201-225. Philadelphia, Pennsylvania. Massam, Dianne. 2001. Pseudo-incorporation in Niuean. Natural Language and Linguistic theory 19: 153-197. Mederdoomian, Karine. 2001. Event structure and Complex Predicates in Persian. Canadian Journal of Linguistics 46 (1/2): 97-125. 254 Mithun, Marianne. 1984. The Evolution of Noun Incorporation. Language, Vol.60, No.4, 847-894. Miyagawa, Shigeru. 1999. Causatives. (ed.) Natsuko Tsujimura, Handbook of Japanese Linguistics, 236-268. Blackwell. Miyagawa, Shigeru. 1980. Complex verbs and lexicon. The Ph.D. dissertation, University of Arizona. McGinnis, Martha.1997. Case and Locality in L-Syntax: evidence from Georgian. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 32, Ed. H. Harley, 1-20. Cambridge, MA: The MIT press. McGinnis, Martha. 2001. Variation in the phase structure of applicatives. In Linguistic Variation Yearbook 1: 105-146. McGinnis, Martha (with Dona Gerdts). 2004. A phase-theoretic analysis of Kinyarwanda multiple applicatives. In Proceedings of the 2003 CLA Annual Conference. Eds. Sophie Burelle and Stanca Somesfalean, 154-165. Mohanan, Tara. 1997. Multodimensionality of representation: NV complex predicates in Hindi. In Alsina et al. (eds). 431-471. Ndayiragije, Juvenal. 2006. The Ergativity Parameter. The view from antipassive. In Ergativity: Emerging Issues. eds. A. Johns, D. Massam, and J. Ndayiragije. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer. Nash, Lea.1994. On BE and HAVE in Georgian. In MITWPL 22, 153-171. eds. H. Harley. Noyer, Rolf. 1997. Features, Positions and Affixes in Autonomous Morphological Structure. New-York: Garland. Pesetsky, David. 1989. Language-Particular Processes and the Earliness Principle. Ms, MIT. Available online at http://web.mit.edu/linguistics/people/faculty/pesetsky/earliness.pdf Pesetsky, David.1995. Zero syntax. Cambridge, MA: The MIT press. Pinker, Stephen. 1989. Learnability and Cognition: The Acquisition of Argument Structure. MIT Press. Pustejovsky, James. 1995. The generative lexicon. Cambridge, MA: The MIT press. Pylkkanen, Liina. 2002. Introducing arguments. Ph.D Dissertation, MIT. 255 Pylkkanen, Liina. 2008. Introducing arguments. Linguistic Inquiry Monographs. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Radford, Andrew. 2004. Minimalist syntax. Exploring the Structure of English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rezak, Milan. 2004. Elements of Cyclic syntax: Agree and merge. The Ph.D dissertation, University of Toronto. Ritter, Elisabeth and Sara Rosen. 1998. Delimiting events in syntax. In The Projection of Arguments, ed. Miriam Butt and Wilhelm Geuder, 135-164. Stanford, California: CSLI Publications. Sadock, Jerrold. 1980. Noun incorporation in Greenlandic. Language 56. 300-319. Serratos, Angelina. 2008. Roots, Functional Heads, and Phases in Chemehuevi. Ph.D. dissertation. University of Arizona. Siddiqi, Daniel. 2009. Syntax within the Word. Economy, allomorphy, and argument selection in Distributed Morphology. Linguistik Aktuell series. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company. Silkirk, Elisabeth. 1982. The Syntax of Words. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Stewart, Thomas. 2001. Georgian Agreement without Extrinsic Ordering. In The Ohio State University Working Papers in Linguistics, vol. 56, 107–133. Stump, Gregory T. 2001. Inflectional Morphology: A Theory of Paradigm Structure [Cambridge Studies in Linguistics 93]. Cambridge: CUP. Topuria, Varlam. 1967. Svanuri Ena. [The Svan Language]. Tbilisi: Tbilisi University Press. Travis, Lisa. 2000. Event structure in Syntax. In Events and Grammatical Objects. (eds.) Carol Tenny and J.Pustejovsky. Stanford: CSLI Publications. Van Gelderen, Elly. 2004. Grammaticalization as Economy. [Linguistik Aktuell 71]. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Vendler, Zeno. 1967. Verbs and times. In Linguistics and Philosophy, ed. Z. Vendler. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Woolford, Elen. 2006. Case and agreement mismatches. Agreement Systems, (ed.) 256 C.Boeckx. 299-316. Amsterdam, Philadelphia: John Benjamins B.V. Zwicky, Arnold. 1985. Heads. Journal of Linguistics 21: 1-30.
* Your assessment is very important for improving the work of artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
advertisement